In this latest book from Bart Ehrman we get a mixed bag of results. On the one hand, he is back in form writing a good popular book on a subject often misunderstood by the lay public. In How Jesus Became God, Ehrman demonstrates that Jesus was worshiped as a god from basically day one. The notion that High Christology developed later, false. On the other hand, I am starting to see a trend in his writing now, wherein he gets right anything he simply culls from existing scholarship and distills for public understanding, but doesn’t always get right everything he tries to add of his own or off the cuff. And the problem with that is that lay readers won’t know which is happening, and thus can’t always trust what he says.
The best rule I can advise is, if Ehrman cites scholarship for a statement he makes, he is at least telling you correctly what that scholarship says (which itself may be wrong, but not by any fault of Ehrman’s). If he doesn’t cite any scholarship for a statement he makes, he might be wrong and you should aim to double-check before relying on it. The rest you have to figure out from the merits of his logic, judging from premise to conclusion. And sometimes that’s solid. Sometimes it’s not.
The rest of this review breaks that down, the good and the bad, into the Devil’s details.
The Main Thesis
The most startling feature of this new book is that in it Ehrman has now completely reversed a position he took against me in Did Jesus Exist (as is well known, I published a detailed critique of that awful book). He now admits that from the very earliest recorded history, indeed even earlier than that, even possibly their very first year, Christians regarded Jesus as a pre-existent divine being. That this was not a later development first encountered in the Gospel of John, for example. “The idea that Jesus is God is not an invention of modern times…it was the view of the very earliest Christians soon after Jesus’s death” (p. 3). Because, “soon after Jesus’s death, the belief in his resurrection led some of his followers to say he was God” (p. 83), by which he means, a god—not identical to the god, a concept Ehrman explains arose much later. Ehrman concludes that at least “some Christians were saying that Jesus was a preexistent being (a ‘later’ view) even before Paul began to write in the 50s–well before our earliest gospel was written” (p. 235), in fact, he admits, “it must have been remarkably early in the Christian tradition,” because “it was in place well before Paul’s letters” and thus did not originate in the time of the gospel of John as has commonly been insisted (p. 276).
And on that point he is right. I have been making this argument for years. I saw the evidence and scholarship proving this even before I wrote Not the Impossible Faith. Now he has looked at all of that, too, and come to the same conclusion. Ehrman also very carefully demarcates a variety of distinctions crucial to this realization, which is one of the best contributions this book makes to the field: Ehrman shows that there was no binary dichotomy of either God or human, but that in fact a whole continuum existed between them, even in Jewish conception. Indeed, far from being unusual, the Jews already believed “divine beings (such as angels) could become human” (p. 5) and that there were many other degrees of divinity between man and God.
Thus, when Ehrman says the first Christians declared Jesus to be god, they were not saying he was identical to God the Father, but that he was a subordinate deity, an archangel appointed to the status of celestial Lord, who existed since the beginning of time (and then, in Christian conception, descended to become incarnate and die, in order to rise again to divine status). Ehrman shows that this was a common type of view within several Jewish theologies of the time, and therefore was not, and would not have been, regarded as contradicting their monotheism. There was nothing un-Jewish about it. In fact it was very typically Jewish.
Ehrman also argues this served as a competing Jewish claim against the claims to divinity of the pagan Emperor, and thus was as much a political statement as a religious one. But that’s a more untenable view. Countless sons of god were worshipped in the Empire, from Romulus to Asclepius, and Jesus was no less safely in heaven, and thus no more a threat to imperial power, than they were. He was, in fact, no politically different than them in any such respect. No more than Antinoos (Hadrian’s deified lover) or Hercules (believed to have been a historical conquerer of the Peloponnesus) or Glycon (a crafted but nevertheless physically living, and deified, ‘snake-man’ worshipped and officially recognized as divine by emperors themselves).
So I think his speculation there is wrong. But he is right about Jesus being deified, and recognized as a pre-existent deity descended into flesh, right out of the gate. And that does disagree with the “traditional” consensus, that such a so-called “high Christology” evolved later over time. But in fact the majority of recent studies in the field have been taking the same view Ehrman now does. So he is joining a rising tide against the traditional consensus, and as I’ve surveyed this literature and evidence myself, I have also concluded that that consensus has been effectively refuted by this new collective of scholarship, dozens of books and articles of which Ehrman cites in his notes.
This of course presents a problem for Ehrman. Because admitting the first Christians regarded Jesus to be a preexistent divine archangel lends unexpected support to mythicism. As many mythicists have been arguing this very point for decades now. And Ehrman can’t have that. So he wants to have it both ways, and throughout the book he tries to argue both that high Christology started right out of the gate, and also that it developed over time. In one respect he is correct, in that the original view of Jesus as a subordinate created being, an archangel assigned the Supreme Lord’s powers, evolved into the far more absurd view that Jesus was literally identical to the One True God. The latter may have been blasphemous to mainstream Jews. But the former was not (as Ehrman extensively proves). And yet the latter did not evolve until long after the first apostles were dead and Christianity had already been established across three continents. This nixes a lot of cherished Christian ideas about how Christianity began and why the Jewish elite originally opposed it.
As Ehrman now explicitly says, identifying “Jesus as messiah, as Lord, as Son of God, as Son of Man–[all] imply, in one sense or another, that Jesus is God.” And yet “in no sense” does that mean he was “understood to be God the Father” (p. 208). This is exactly what I argued in Not the Impossible Faith, and which Ehrman once denounced as misinformed (DJE, p. 167). Yet now he admits I was entirely correct. Based on past experience, I won’t hold my breath for his apology. But it’s nice to see him on board now at least.
But Ehrman also wants to claim that Christianity “must” have started with a low exaltation Christology (because historicity is in serious trouble if it didn’t), and (he supposes) one sect of it just super-rapidly (in just a year or two?) elevated that to a high incarnation Christology, even though there is no evidence of there ever being that first stage. Ehrman only tries to invent that evidence out of a fundamentalist reading of Mark and a few passages in Acts and Paul that he insists on reading in conjunction with a number of circular presumptions about what went on in their formation.
The Invented Evidence
The irony of historicity defenders today is that they are forced to act like Christian apologists, by inventing readings and claims against the obvious, inventing evidence that doesn’t exist, contriving harmonizations of contradictions based on ad hoc suppositions of convenience, resorting to egregiously fallacious logic, and then, most astonishing of all, reading the Bible literally. Ehrman has done all of this before.
In this case, Ehrman resorts to a literalist reading of Mark, treating the text essentially just as Christian fundamentalists do. But Mark is not writing literal history. He is writing allegory (as I have thoroughly demonstrated, citing both evidence and scholarship on the point, in On the Historicity of Jesus, ch. 10). So reading Mark literally is to get exactly wrong everything he is saying. Mark actually does not say anything about where Jesus came from and never discusses cosmology or theology. Moreover, Mark is defending Pauline Christianity decades after Paul, and yet Paul was already firmly and unapologetically assuming a high incarnation Christology, it was in fact the only Christology known to him, and was so unopposed by any alternative that in his letters it needed no defense. So why would his followers decades later reverse course and depict a low exaltation Christology instead? This makes no sense as an interpretation of what Mark is doing.
And here is where Ehrman falls off the rails of sound method: as in DJE, despite no longer being a Christian, he is still toeing the Christian party line that Mark is a history book and is intending to tell his readers what actually happened, as some straightforward story. But that’s contrary to every sound literary analysis. Mark is fabricating a symbolic allegory. He thus cannot be taken literally at anything. He is not portraying any Christology. He is assembling lessons about Christian life and the gospel, and doing so with myths. The most obvious demonstration of this is the fig tree incident, where it is obvious Mark in no way actually means Jesus withered a fig tree for the absurd reason that it wasn’t bearing figs out of season. The fig tree represents the Jewish temple cult, and its withering represents what God allowed to happen to it, and why (as a result of the destruction of Jerusalem by the Romans in 70 A.D.). So when Mark has Jesus adopted by God at his baptism, Mark is not trying to say that that is historically what happened, any more than he was trying to claim Jesus actually withered a fig tree for no sane reason. The baptism scene is a model for Christian baptism. This is what baptism meant in the church: adoption by God, cleansing one of their sins for all time. Jesus is thus simply a mythic stand-in for every model Christian. This is a story not about Jesus, but about baptism. And even insofar as it is about history at all, it only embodied the claim (true or not) that the Baptist cult endorsed the Jesus cult as their superior and successor.
Once we see what Mark is doing, we must realize he can supply us with no evidence of an exaltation Christology phase of Christianity, much less a phase that was phased out within his own sect decades before he wrote. Because he is not writing about how the church originated. Or about the cosmological foundations of his Christology. And once we drop the insupportable assumption to the contrary, we have no reason left to think there ever was such a phase. Ehrman of course needs there to be, because if there wasn’t, the historicity of Jesus becomes very hard to maintain. He needs historicity. So he needs exaltation Christology. So he needs Mark to be a historian. And so he ends up acting like a Christian fundamentalist, and treats Mark as though he is writing a history of the church’s origins, when in fact he is writing mythology for decades-later Christian life and ideas.
But on the point that Christianity began with a high incarnation Christology, many scholars concur with Ehrman and me. It was once a fringe view that has now grown to a large and fairly decisive mainstream challenge to the old guard. It is obviously the correct view. As Ehrman points out, the evidence just can’t be denied. Paul knew no other version of Christianity. For Paul, Jesus was a pre-existent divine being whom God used as the agent of creation, and only later sent to assume a body of flesh and thereby die, and thus become an instrument of salvation for the corrupt world order. Ehrman tries to squeeze a few years (or days?) of low exaltation Christology into Christian history before that. But this is just his own conjecture. There is no evidence of it in Paul. And Mark is decades later, is not at odds with Paul, and not writing literal history.
All of Ehrman’s other evidence consists solely of showing (from Paul and Acts) that there was an early belief that Jesus was declared the Son of God at his resurrection. What he fails to consider is that Jesus was re-declared so, in other words, reaffirmed to his previous status, which he had relinquished (as Philippians 2 says), having shed that status to become human and die. Ehrman at no point considers this alternative, even though it is self-evidently what the Philippians hymn is saying–a hymn which Ehrman agrees is pre-Pauline and thus among the earliest recoverable Christian tradition. In contrast with that, Ehrman has nothing comparable supporting his theory. I have to conclude his exaltation-phase theory is baseless. It hangs on the weakest and vaguest of evidence, and then only when bolstered by convenient speculations, while contradicting directly all the evidence we have.
Errors
This is a good book for beginners, as it explains a lot of things in the study of religion that experts take for granted but often forget everyone else often doesn’t know. But I still worry that Ehrman, being a little lazy, miseducates a lot by getting facts slightly wrong (and sometimes more than slightly), as if he were an amateur. I don’t expect everything to be correct (we can’t know everything) but sometimes his mistakes are not the kind we should expect him to make, and this happens far too often, two factors that combine to make this defect of the book worthy of remark.
Many examples are no big deal, except that a reader who doesn’t know they are wrong might cite or quote this book on this or that point, assuming what it seems to say is correct, and get embarrassed by someone more knowledgeable, or reach incorrect conclusions from mistaken premises. Other examples are a little more serious, or even a bit astonishing.
For instance…
(1) Ehrman says Christians regarded Jesus to be God’s “unique son” (p. 7), but it’s not clear what he means by that. All Christians baptized were God’s son, so Jesus wasn’t unique, he was only the first (hence firstborn). He was uniquely assigned the powers and role of Lord, but that’s not quite the same thing. Likewise, Ehrman says, “when the earliest Christians talked about Jesus becoming the son of god at his resurrection, they were saying something truly remarkable about him” (p. 232), which can’t be entirely true, because Christians were saying this about themselves, saying they themselves were the adopted sons of God (OHJ, p. 108). It can’t have been more remarkable for Jesus than it was for a Christian. Maybe this was remarkable in certain respects, but if so, it was remarkable not because it was said of Jesus, but because it was said of all baptized Christians. This includes the Christian concept of inheritance, which is stated by Paul many times: we shall inherit the kingdom of God, not just Jesus will, because like Jesus, we are all sons and thus heirs. Jesus is special only in being the firstborn, in other words the primary heir. The nuance is important for understanding just what the Christians were actually preaching. Ehrman seems not to notice.
(2) That’s the most trivial example. Another is when Ehrman defines “henotheism [as] the view that there are other gods, but there is only one God who is to be worshiped” (p. 53). That’s not entirely correct. Henotheists can sometimes worship other gods as the supreme God’s subordinates or manifestations (as we see in pagan henotheism). This is an example of a minor mistake that could mislead lay readers, who expect more accuracy, and might go on to insist this is what henotheism means–when, really, it’s not, it’s just one variety of henotheism. It’s a little strange to see Wikipedia outperforming Ehrman on defining a basic concept in the study of religions. What Ehrman is defining is monolatry. But again, this is a small error and not that big a deal (after all, one will find common, non-specialist dictionaries repeating the same error).
(3) Another small but problematic error is that Ehrman seems not to know the First Principles of Origen mostly only survives in the Latin translation of Rufinus, who altered everything to be more in tune with orthodox thinking, a fact Jerome complained about explicitly. So in fact what is said there are not the views of Origen, nor maybe even of any Christian of the 3rd century, but the views of Rufinus, and anti-Origen orthodoxists of the 4th century. This is often not known in the field and is thus an easy mistake to make, so again this error is not egregious. But nevertheless, it does undermine everything Ehrman says about this text (p. 313), which is based on his assumption that it contains the early third century thoughts of Origen.
(4) But things get weirder when Ehrman says “most people at the time Jesus lived, apart from the upper-crust Roman elite, did not have last names” (p. 112-13). This is wrong twice over. All Roman citizens, regardless of social status, even the poorest of the poor, even freed slaves, had the trinomen, and therefore had what we mean by last names (a surname or family name). It was actually a fundamental indicator of citizenship. And nearly everyone else had the same kind of last name our last names used to be: Johnson, for example, is what it literally says, John’s son. Jesus Benjoseph, for example, would have been recognized and in documents even used as Jesus’ name, if his father’s name was indeed Joseph. That’s a last name. It’s not clear why Ehrman thinks our last names are in any sense different, apart from the trivia of how we grammatically construct them now. (Even if he means a persisting family name, that’s in the Roman trinomen, which all Romans of all social positions held. Newly minted citizens might have invented or borrowed ones to get their new family tradition started, but that’s no different from so-called Ellis Island names today. [Which were not actually assigned at or by Ellis Island, but many immigrants deliberately chose to change their names around that time.]
(5) More worrying is when Ehrman seems ignorant of actual Mishnah law, and the latest literature on crucifixion, and on crucifixion’s use in Judaism (pp. 256-57). Contrary to what Ehrman implies, Paul is not making any distinction in his letters between Jewish stoning procedure and “crucifixion,” nor would it make sense to, since the Jewish curse law he cites in Galatians, that cursed is anyone hanged on a tree, not only applies to those stoned by Jewish courts, but is even in fact a quotation of that very Deuteronomic law. From Paul alone, there is no indication he ever meant or imagined Roman crucifixion anywhere in his letters. I can understand making the inference based on the Gospels (if, like Ehrman, you think the Gospels are history books). But I can’t understand why Ehrman would suggest it’s intrinsic in Paul’s language, or necessary to Paul’s soteriology. It’s not. (OHJ, pp. 61-62.)
(6) Or when Ehrman says it’s “widely thought” that the gospel of John “did not rely on” the other gospels, which is demonstrably false, both as to the fact of it, and as to the “widely thought” part. Nearly every major expert on John has concluded otherwise (Waetjen, Barrett, Cribbs, Dodd, Parker, Bailey, even Raymond Brown: OHJ, pp. 268-69). And the evidence is pretty undeniable that that is the case. There actually is no valid argument for independence. The notion that John did not always copy his source verbatim, for example, is struck dead by the fact that copying verbatim is actually an unusual way to use a source in antiquity. The way John uses his sources by rewriting them in his own fashion was actually the method of redacting and coopting material most assiduously taught in schools of the period, the very schools we know the authors of the Gospels had passed through, as doing so was the only way to acquire the command of compositional Greek exhibited in their work. Meanwhile, John copies and responds to so many things in the Synoptics that it simply makes no sense to suppose he is not in actual fact using and responding to them (e.g., OHJ, pp. 487-89, 503-05).
(7) Or when Ehrman says, “the Romans who did crucify [Jesus] had no concern to obey Jewish law and virtually no interest in Jewish sensitivities” and therefore were under no obligation to take Jesus down for burial once he had died (pp. 156-59). The facts are exactly the contrary, as proved extensively by Josephus, who explicitly discusses this fact, and even cites imperial decrees commanding that Roman authorities respect Jewish laws and not interfere with their being carried out (for evidence and scholarship on this point, see my chapter on “The Burial of Jesus in Light of Jewish Law” in The Empty Tomb). In Ehrman’s clumsy attempt to prove the Romans did not make such accommodations, he fails to cite a single example from Judea before the Jewish War, when and where that imperial decree was still in effect. He only cites examples from outside Judea, and not involving Jews or Judea. That’s a fallacy, citing a general practice that is well known not to apply to Jews and Judea at the time, as evidence that it did. This is like arguing that women must have high average testosterone levels by citing abundant evidence that men do.
Ehrman thus mistakenly thinks the same rules applied to Jews and in Judea of the early first century, as to everyone and everywhere and everywhen else, when in fact this imperial decree documented and discussed by Josephus proves the Jews were treated exceptionally in just this respect. Ehrman shows no sign of even knowing this decree existed, or any of Josephus’s discussion of it. Ehrman instead botches his reading of Philo, whose testimony Ehrman gets exactly wrong, and of archaeology, which Ehrman likewise gets wrong.
As to the first point (Philo), in the passage Ehrman discusses, Philo is actually arguing that the established practice was to honor holy days. And what was against standard practice was the choice not to do this, which is why failing to do so is for Philo a criminal accusation against the prefect of Egypt in his case. Ehrman confuses this somehow as arguing that it “wasn’t” the standard practice, and that refusing the legally required burial was the norm. That’s simply not what Philo is saying. He is saying quite the opposite of that (as I show in my chapter for The Empty Tomb).
As to the second point (archaeology), the fact that we have recovered the bones of a crucified person from an ossuary confirms that in fact convicts did receive formal burial, because the only way those bones could have gotten there is by having been buried somewhere to retrieve them from for secondary burial, usually six months to a year later. Ehrman shows no sign of knowing that Mishnah law mandated that the Sanhedrin itself bury convicts in a special graveyard for the condemned (see, again, my chapter on this in The Empty Tomb), who could then be recovered for secondary burial later, after the flesh rotted from the bones. Thus the archaeology does not support Ehrman on this; it contradicts him.
(8) Ehrman also falsely reports that Pilate showed no respect for Jewish sensitivities. To the contrary, when he tried to violate the Jewish law against icons, Pilate acquiesced to Jewish law when the Jews launched a protest. And if the Jews would be willing to slit their own throats en masse to enforce that law, they would likewise any other he tried to interfere with. And failing that, they would have brought a legal case against him to the emperor, for violating imperial edicts, which in fact they eventually did (for an unrelated offense), and he was deposed. Josephus thus does not say Pilate abolished or ignored all Jewish laws; he simply records those specific instances in which he did, which were all specific political acts serving Pilate’s imperial interests, and not a blanket ignoring of all Jewish laws. Exceptional cases are presented exactly as such, particularly as stirring outrage and violence against Pilate’s sporadic violations of the imperial decree. Missing nuances like this is typical of Christian apologists. It’s a bit strange coming from a secular historian.
(9) Some of Ehrman’s mistakes could just be bad writing. For example, he says, “In none of the stories of divine humans born from the union of a god and a mortal is the mortal a virgin” (p. 24). When I first looked at this line, nearly two hundred people had highlighted it in the kindle edition, showing the danger of Ehrman’s lazy writing (or thinking? or research?) miseducating the public. As an expert, I know enough to imagine that what he actually means is “remains” a virgin, not “was” a virgin. Certainly many divine conceptions in Greek and Roman legend were bestowed upon virgins, in fact that was a common trope (for obvious narrative reasons: the only way to be sure the conception was supernatural is if the mother had never yet been with a man, especially, if such was the case, whichever man she was at the time married or betrothed to). See Virgin Birth: It’s Pagan, Guys. Get Over It.
For example, Plutarch says legend had it the mother of Romulus was a virgin, impregnated mysteriously by the god Mars while she was locked away (specifically to prevent that very thing). One might suppose this was accomplished sexually, but that isn’t really as relevant a distinction as Ehrman makes out. And here yet again Ehrman simply acts like a Christian apologist, arguing as if this distinction matters, when in fact it doesn’t: all syncretism combines the borrowed concept, here a god impregnating a virgin to establish divine patrimony, with a native concept, here the common Jewish disgust for sex, which motivated the Judaizing of the borrowed mytheme by simply deleting the sexual element from it (see That Luxor Thing). But even the absence of sex is attested in pagan mythology. Most famously, in the case of Perseus, a golden shower (drops of gold falling from the ceiling into his mother’s vagina) is far closer to Mary being overshadowed by the Holy Spirit (just as magical a substance, which just as surely went into her womb to impregnate her). So she remained as much a virgin as Mary did, as even early Christians conceded (Justin, for example, had to admit Perseus was born of a virgin). There were also sexless conceptions of other kinds, for example in the myth that has Hera giving birth to Hephaestus by act of will rather than sexual union. So the Jews did not want for precedent in pagan mythography.
So did Ehrman simply misstate what he meant, by accident? In the example he cites, Ehrman says the woman was not a virgin even before the god visited her (Alcmena, who “had already had sex with her husband”), so bad writing does not appear to be the best explanation of this error. It certainly looks like Ehrman is falsely saying there were no women in these divine conception legends who were virgins when first approached by a god, which is incorrect. Even the mother of Alexander the Great claimed God had impregnated her on her wedding night (in the form of a thunderbolt; later the story became it was a giant snake), before her husband had consummated their marriage. And obviously she had to, otherwise Alexander’s divine patrimony would be in question. Similarly the famous Osiris myth, carved into the very pyramids, describes the God getting with the mother on her wedding night, disguised as her husband, before her real husband gets his turn (see, again, That Luxor Thing). And precisely the same was being said of Plato in the Christian era (as Origen reported, “For some have thought fit…to relate as a possible thing that Plato was the son of Amphictione, Ariston being prevented from having marital intercourse with his wife until she had given birth to him with whom she was pregnant by Apollo,” Against Celsus 37). So Ehrman’s example of Alcmena is disingenuous and deeply misleading.
(10) It’s all the stranger when Ehrman says early on in the book (p. 18) that “I don’t know of any other cases,” besides Jesus, “in ancient Greek or Roman thought of this kind of ‘god-man’, where an already existing divine being is said to be born of a mortal woman.” And then later he discusses exactly such an example: Proteus Peregrinus; as if Ehrman had forgotten he had just claimed he didn’t know of any! As Ehrman correctly reports (p. 36), Peregrinus was said to have claimed to be the god Proteus in the flesh, despite having been born of a woman. And that’s not the only example. Philostratus reported the same claim was made of Apollonius of Tyana. And Plutarch reports the belief that Romulus had said he was a pre-existent deity (named Quirinus) who became incarnate (and then died and “returned” to heaven), despite also being born to a mortal woman. Ehrman himself says Moses was likewise thought by some Jews to be a pre-existent divine being born subsequently of a woman (p. 82). So it’s almost as if the Ehrman who wrote the rest of the book wasn’t talking to the Ehrman who wrote the first part of the book. Perhaps he imagined these examples were ambiguous as to whether they were claiming to have a human mother or denying it, but there is no evidence they were claiming otherwise. So that seems more like an opinion than a fact.
(11) I also found it weird (as I already noted above) that Ehrman would claim Jesus and the Roman Emperors (and one could perhaps understand him to also mean the Greco-Macedonian Kings before that) were the only historical people in antiquity called the son of god (p. 355). But all Christians called each other the sons of God (they were adopted as such through their baptism, as Paul repeatedly and clearly says). Plato was believed to be the son of god (Apollo). Alexander’s incarnated snake-god Glycon was also explicitly the son of god (again Apollo) and Roman emperors even paid him homage as such. Yes, Glycon wasn’t a real “person” per se, we know he was just a snake, but he was still a living, historical being, whom even Emperors recognized as an existing incarnate god on earth and hailed as the son of a god, without any political ramifications. This deeply undermines Ehrman’s entire thesis about the politics of calling Jesus the son of God. The Jews even called angels the sons of God. And again, Christians called themselves the sons of God. So it doesn’t look like a political challenge at all.
(12) There are also statements Ehrman makes that one might suppose are not errors but differences of opinion, yet he portrays his opinion as overwhelmingly dominant when in fact there is a large number of widely respected experts who disagree. And failing to concede or even mention that looks too easily like a deception perpetrated on his readers. For example, Ehrman calls arguments for Q “formidable” when in fact they are not even good. Like him, I used to think there were formidable arguments for Q, because that’s what everyone said. Until I actually read all the arguments for Q (and arguments against). And then I felt betrayed by what the “consensus” had told me. This is one of several revelations that led me to conclude the “consensus” in this field is simply not trustworthy.
Ehrman hasn’t learned this lesson yet. Ironically, considering this very book of his illustrates extensively how wrong the presumed consensus was, about the very subject Ehrman is elucidating. He trusted the consensus, so much so he even cited it against me. Then he checked…and found the consensus had betrayed him. Now he sides against it. In other words, now he sides with me. And as he discovered, he isn’t alone. Experts had been proving this for decades…and the “consensus” simply ignored them, or just gainsaid them without any sound argument. Because the “consensus” can’t ever be wrong, evidence be damned. Ehrman just hasn’t realized that this is not an isolated case. What he found for this, is true about almost everything he cites “the consensus” for. Including Q. And the method of criteria. And so on.
It’s kind of sad that Ehrman goes on failing to learn this lesson, and thus goes on promoting a certainty in the field that does not exist and in fact has been deeply undermined by many of his peers. I think this makes him a bad educator, placing his ego ahead of accurately informing the public. It would be different if he actually presented his arguments for the claims he makes that are challenged by the community, and thus admitted arguments had to be made to assert his own certainty, rather than using a fallacious, even dishonest, appeal to authority instead…an authority that doesn’t even relevantly exist.
-:-
(I also disagree with Ehrman’s silly nonrationalistic epistemic relativism, essentially a historian’s version of Gould’s non-overlapping magisteria [pp. 132, 143-47, 163-65, 172-73, 187-88], which he convolutedly designed in order not to offend religious believers. But I needn’t fisk any of that, because his treatment of the philosophy of history here is sufficiently contradictory and confusing as to be almost unintelligible. The best antidote is already my book Proving History, so I refer anyone interested in that question there. I won’t dwell on it further here.)
-:-
Despite all the things like I have surveyed above, it has to be said that Ehrman also fills this book with a lot of correct information, too, much in fact that most people don’t know and even many scholars deny, and a lot of that he backs with evidence, cited scholarship, and good argument. It is thus useful in that regard. For instance, Ehrman gets ancient demonology right, thus de facto refuting Maurice Casey, who denied everything Ehrman here proves correct. Casey, for instance, mistakenly cites 1 Enoch to claim no demons lived on earth; while Ehrman realizes it says the opposite, and understands the significance of this for understanding early Christianity (e.g., p. 64).
Just be careful to double check any claim Ehrman makes that he doesn’t back with sources and evidence. Especially claims as to what didn’t exist or never happened, claims that require far more pervasive familiarity with ancient history than your average biblical textual critic gets in school. I am most surprised by this because he should have already taught himself his lesson. This whole book shows he was wrong about a lot that he once insisted wasn’t true or didn’t exist. He even explicitly says so, several times, throughout the book. So he ought to know how precarious such claims are if you don’t thoroughly research them first. Yet, alas. We have all the errors surveyed above. It’s unfortunate.
Nifty Gets
It’s nevertheless nice to see Ehrman finally on board now arguing things we mythicists have been arguing for decades. For example, he most explicitly admits now that “saying what Jews thought is itself highly problematic, since lots of different Jews thought lots of different things. It would be like asking what Christians think today” (p. 50). Many of his arguments in DJE are based on his insistence that Jews only ever monolithically thought one thing, and would never ever think anything different. He now admits, for example, that many Jews not just believed in but worshiped angels alongside God. The idea of worshiping subordinate deities, and still claiming to be monotheists, was not alien to them at all. Indeed, he now admits that when rabbinical sources condemn an idea as heresy, this means there were in fact Jews who believed that, not that no Jews would (p. 69). In fact, Ehrman says, the more vehemently the rabbis condemn a belief, the more extensively that belief was probably actually held by Jews of the time. Among these is the belief that there was more than one worship-worthy god in heaven. He cites scholarship thoroughly demonstrating this.
Ehrman also now agrees that Philo already attests a Jewish theology in which the Logos is the firstborn Son of God and the eternal Image of God, the same being Jesus was identified with (p. 75). (He overlooks the passage where Philo says a Jesus named in the OT is this very same being, but that’s not unexpected, since it requires some cross-checking to discover: see OHJ, pp. 200-05.) He also finds Philo attesting a Jewish belief that Moses was a pre-existent divine being who became incarnate to live on earth and then ascend back to his station in heaven, establishing yet another Jewish precedent for Christian incarnation Christology (p. 82).
Ehrman also dares to admit that Paul’s letters are weirdly silent about a historical Jesus. “I sometimes give my students an assignment to read through all of Paul’s writings and list everything Paul indicates Jesus said and did,” Ehrman reports, and “my students are surprised to find that they don’t even need a three-by-five card to list them” (p. 89). He just doesn’t connect the dots. For example, he freely uses arguments from the silence in Paul’s letters that the story of Joseph of Arimathea was invented later and not known to Paul (p. 141); yet the exact same reasoning entails all the historicizing tales of Jesus were invented later and not known to Paul. Just a little consistency would lead Ehrman to the mythicist position on Paul.
Ehrman also finds evidence in Paul that explicitly states that Paul and his Christian congregations simply assumed without argument that Jesus was in fact an angel. He found this demonstrated by the grammatical analysis of Gal. 4:14 performed by several previous scholars (p. 250). I had not discovered that argument myself, and it is intriguing, supporting my case for that same conclusion in OHJ.
One of my favorite observations from Ehrman is his admission that “storytellers were apt to add details to stories that were vague, or to give names to people otherwise left nameless in a tradition, or to add named individuals to stories that originally mentioned only nameless individuals or undifferentiated groups of individuals,” citing Bruce Metzger’s famous article “Names for the Nameless,” in which “he showed all the traditions of people who were unnamed in New Testament stories receiv[ed] names later,” which if visible in the written record, could and would have operated on any oral record preceding our earliest written record (p. 154). Details therefore do not make the stories more convincing. I found this very same fact confirmed in studies of urban legends, which I cite in OHJ. It’s worth noting that in urban legends that get “background facts” added to them (like history and geography), those facts often are accurate. Yet the story they are added to is wholly fabricated. Take note of that. It’s almost exactly what Luke did to Mark and Matthew.
Ehrman also presents some good arguments against the Christian apologetical claim that no one would claim Jesus was raised unless they knew the tomb was empty (pp. 7, 174), and he makes a good case for the bereavement vision hypothesis (which certainly makes sense if we start from the premise that Jesus existed: pp. 194-96). He takes several positions stalwartly against Christian apologetics, positions which also (inadvertently) support my case for the non-existence of Jesus, such as that “there was nothing categorically different about any” of the appearances to any of the first apostles, “they were all appearances from heaven” (p. 206).
But Sad Deceptions
Unfortunately, Ehrman then distorts the evidence in other places, leaving out damning information and thus disturbingly mis-informing his readers.
Here is an example:
“[Christians] pointed to passages in the Bible that talked about one who suffered and was then vindicated, passages such as Isaiah 53 and Psalm 22. Jews, though, had a ready response: these passages are not talking about the messiah. And you can see by reading them yourself, in fact the word messiah never occurs in them.” (p. 116)
This is disturbingly misleading in several ways. First, Ehrman had earlier explained that Jews used a number of different ways to refer to their messiah, including “chosen one” or “elect one” (e.g., p. 66). Guess what the dying-and-vindicated man in Isaiah 53 is called? You guessed it, God’s elect, in other words “the chosen one” or “elect one.” So it is disingenuous of him to claim the word “messiah” was not in them therefore they were not messianic. Jews did not restrict passages as being about the messiah to only those that explicitly used the word messiah. Ehrman himself knows this, even says so elsewhere in the very same book, yet here his argument requires his readers forget it. It is thus fallacious on the facts.
Worse, all actual Jewish writing that ever discusses Isaiah 53 says it is about the messiah. All of it. For example, this is simply assumed without argument in the Talmud, where incidentally its rabbinical sources conclude that this very scripture predicted the messiah would die and be resurrected. This is the second thing wrong with Ehrman’s statements: he omits all the evidence telling against him, all the evidence instead arguing that the Jews actually did imagine a dying and rising messiah (whom Ehrman admits the Jews would regard as in some sense a god), and even saw such a thing in the very passages he says Christians were pointing to. They also were not scandalized by this, and saw no need to be defensive about it. It’s simply taken for granted, no argument needed. Thus, Ehrman’s portrayal of Jews as being incapable of imagining such a thing is false on its face. There is no evidence Jews had a problem coming up with the idea. They often did.
The third thing wrong with this is that Ehrman strangely “forgets” to mention one other passage anywhere in this discussion, Daniel 9, which actually does have the word messiah in it, and actually does say the messiah would die (and, incidentally, also gives a mathematical prediction as to when this would happen that on the simplest calculation gives us the era of Pontius Pilate). It also says a great and final atonement for all sins would be effected upon or shortly after that death; and Isaiah 53 says the chosen one’s death would in one blow atone for all sins. It would be nearly impossible not to see these passages as referring to the same person, and we have some evidence early Jews may indeed have made that connection (in the pre-Christian Dead Sea “Melchizedek” scroll). Ehrman might dispute that (the scroll is badly damaged so its exact meaning can be debated), but he can’t dispute the fact that the passages are easily seen as referring to the same figure, and he can’t dispute the fact that in Daniel the Jewish scriptures did in fact predict a messiah’s death, in a passage that explicitly uses the word messiah and explicitly says he will die.
Ehrman has confusingly tried to dismiss that latter point by claiming that Daniel 9 was about a past figure, but that is moot: by the dawn of the first century, few Jews were seeing it that way, but regarding Daniel as an as-yet-unfulfilled scripture, and therefore not about a past figure (it is actually undeniable that the Melchizedek scroll sees it that way, and Josephus attests to others who did as well). And Ehrman is perfectly capable of understanding this. Because he says exactly the same thing of Daniel 7: “However one interprets Daniel in its original second-century BCE context, what is clear is that eventually in some Jewish circles it came to be thought that” it was referring to a “future deliverer” (p. 65). As for Daniel 7, so for Daniel 9. For the exact same reasons. Ehrman thus doesn’t even follow his own advice. Once again, much like a Christian apologist.
This evidence is damning to Ehrman’s argument here. Yet he knows all of this. So his omitting it is deeply troubling to me. It looks like an attempt to deceive, to doctor and alter the evidential record so that only his conclusion seems viable, and not even tell anyone about the evidence contradicting him, much less attempt to wriggle out of it. This same behavior plagues his entire case for historicity…
Ehrman Still Stuck on Bad Arguments for Historicity
Ehrman again just asserts without any evidence or arguments that stories Matthew adds to Mark he “obviously got them from somewhere” (p. 95), when it seems more obvious to me (and countless other scholars in the field) that Matthew is himself inventing them. He isn’t getting them “from” somewhere. So why does Ehrman leap instead to the position of the Christian apologist? No explanation. He says the same for Luke. This is the same thing Ehrman did in DJE: he just fabricates non-existent, unattested sources left and right, without basis, evidence, or argument. And then uses them to declare his conclusion a certainty. Meanwhile, he then admits John made everything up. But why does he concede this for John, but not then make the obvious next step and realize as for John, so for all?
Likewise again Ehrman defends the method of criteria, even though all experts who have published specific studies of them have found them irreparably flawed and unusable (as I document, extensively, in Proving History). Ehrman just hasn’t caught up with the literature. Yet he is telling his readers that his conclusions here are “taken as a fact by almost all critical scholars,” which isn’t true. Indeed, his fake sources are doubted by a great many leading experts. As is the notion, for example, that anything repeated in multiple sources all goes back to Jesus. Obviously the nativity narratives do not go back to Jesus, for instance, no matter how many independent sources we have for them (there are indeed at least six). As nearly all critical scholars agree. So Ehrman isn’t accurately representing even the consensus, much less checking if the consensus is correct. This is bizarre, because he admits the stories in the Gospels have layers of embellishment on them (p. 96), and yet then he says “Jesus is said to have been crucified by Pontius Pilate in both Mark and John, and there are independent aspects of the story reported in M and L. And so that’s probably what happened…” But leading experts on John conclude John got this from Mark (John even quotes mark verbatim in several places), and M and L just mean the things Matthew and Luke add to Mark independent of each other. In other words, “layers of embellishment.”
Ehrman’s methodology thus makes no logical sense. He admits the core facts have been embellished, and yet the moment he encounters one of those embellishments, he declares it an independent source for the core story being embellished thereby! Imagine this. I hear a story from Sue, and I embellish it. Ehrman comes along and says Sue’s story must then be true, because my embellishments must have a source independent of Sue! That is Ehrman’s argument.
Ehrman also selectively cites his evidence to distort reality. Because in reality, the sources don’t agree on this detail. Some say the agents of King Jannaeus killed Jesus. Some say he was crucified by Herod. The only source, literally the only single source, that says he was crucified by Pilate, or even Romans at all, is Mark. All other sources repeating that detail simply get it from Mark, and embellish it. So not only is there only one source, not several, but when we look at all the sources, we see several divergent accounts of who killed Jesus, not one. Even by Ehrman’s own faulty assumptions (he gullibly trusts the interpolation in 1 Thessalonians 2 to be authentic), Ehrman must concede Paul says it was the Jews who killed Jesus; no mention of even the Romans, much less Pilate.
This illogical labor on Ehrman’s part to slap heaping wodges of duct tape on the whole historicity thesis in a desperate attempt to keep it from crumbling only leads Ehrman to say silly things. For instance, when he says Paul “never says that Jesus declared himself to be divine.” That is a silly thing to say, as it is the very worst argument from silence conceivable (ironically for someone so hostile to arguments from silence–when they don’t go his way). In actual fact Paul never discusses Jesus even having a ministry, much less teaching or saying anything at all during it. In fact, Paul never refers to anything Jesus ever said before his death (and indeed one should ask why!), except as whispered to the prophets, which did in fact proclaim his divinity, and yet Paul says Jesus taught him the gospel on their first (revelatory) meeting (Galatians 1).
So certainly Paul believed, and taught, that Jesus declared himself to be divine (in the sense Ehrman rightly and carefully demarcates, as a subordinate divine being), since everywhere Paul talks about the gospel, the divinity of Jesus is essential to it, and is credited as having been communicated to the apostles by Jesus (by revelation–both directly, and indirectly through his influence on the Biblical prophets). Indeed there is no conceivable reason why Paul’s hallucinations of a celestial Jesus (real or pretended) would ever have been coy about it. So surely we should not conclude that Paul attests to a time when Jesus wasn’t claiming to be divine. There is no evidence of that in Paul. The more so as Paul believes Jesus was announcing his future triumph and divinity to the prophets already in the OT, and thus in fact had long been discussing it. Paul never seems aware of any time Jesus wasn’t saying this.
One Big Dropped Ball
In Ehrman’s last chapter he discusses later developments (such as of the Middle Ages) and how Christians evolved into insisting upon a trinitarian monotheism even though Christendom had never embraced such a thing before. What I found lacking here is any real explanation of why they were so murderously obsessed with doing that. Why did Christian “orthodoxists” so desperately need to affirm only “one” God, and why at the same time insist Jesus and the Holy Spirit were the same exact thing as that one God? What was so repugnant, or dangerous, or destructive of their other beliefs, in the notion of just embracing three deities, or simply saying Jesus was an archangel doing God’s will, as Paul was teaching in the first place? It can’t be said this obsession was simply intrinsic, since there were countless Christians content with alternatives, both at the faith’s origin and in every century ever after. So why were these other Christians not content with them?
Ehrman offers just one theory in a couple of sentences, undefended (p. 343): the view that Christianity was actually obsessed with political unity and sought to enforce that by demanding theological unity: one god, therefore one empire. But that doesn’t really explain anything. The Romans sought unity without having to obsess over monotheism, and so did the Jews (as Ehrman’s very book establishes). Likewise the Chinese. And just as the Roman Empire had subordinate rulers, so could its cosmo-theological analog. So why could they not accept Jesus as the kind of deity Paul recognized: God’s viceroy? Ehrman’s only preferred theory does not answer that question. Indeed, it seems to just repeat the question as if it were an answer. “Why did the Christians obsess over this extremist unity concept? Because the Christians were obsessed with an extremist unity concept.”
Ehrman also does not examine Eastern Orthodox, Coptic, Ethiopian, or Nestorian or Assyrian Christianity, for example. They did not necessarily follow the Nicene creed, or interpret it the same way. I found this to be an unfortunate defect of the book, which could have, and should have, included an informative chapter on such histories, because they would inform the Western tradition by contrast and comparison.
Conclusion
In conclusion, there are a lot of errors in this book, from the trivial to the serious. But overall it does soundly establish the key point that Jesus was regarded as a pre-existent incarnate divine being from the earliest recorded history of Christianity, even in fact before the writings of Paul, and that this was not even remarkable within Judaism. The specifically trinitarian concept of Jesus being identical to the supreme God he shows did indeed only arise much later. But that even Jews accepted a spectrum of divinity, and not a binary, Ehrman also well proves. He thus establishes a cornerstone of the mythicist thesis. And destroys a cherished cornerstone of liberal Christian historical interpretation. In defense of historicity, meanwhile, this book adds nothing. In fact, it takes quite a bit a way. The pillars are crumbling.
Ah, so you can read others notes and highlights in kindle books? Did not know that. Is it possible to read your notes Richard, in say, DJE? :)?
hmmm, seems you have to have an actual kindle reader for that :/
I like Ehrman’s earlier work on textual criticism and I suppose like many atheists it was my introduction to the whole problems with the Jesus story thing. However, DJE was a nasty hatchet job and his reaction to the criticism has been to double-down and accuse mythicists of being nasty rude meanies, while hosting snide personal remarks about them (I am a subscriber/member of his blog so I saw the comments and his responses to them).
My biggest problem with Ehrman at the moment is his appeals to authority and his qualifications snobbery. The fact is Ehrman is a well qualified textual critic but that does not make him a historian, and his appeals to authority are appeals to the authorities of Christian colleges. He will occasionally allow that this might be a problem but it needs to be dragged out of him.
It seems however that he has actually started to do the historian thing and go back to the source materials himself and his ground is shifting although he doesn’t display much of this shift on his blog. If his ground shifts too far however it is going to cause him problems, as in a few talks I’ve watched his closest friends within the academy and also his wife are committed Christians. There is also the problem that since the historicity debate has flared up, his paying audience has swung much more Christian. There was a time when he was considered close to being the Antichrist by conservative Christians, now he is the saviour of the historical Jesus, and getting quite a following for it. I actually feel some sympathy for him if he’s teetering.
So maybe it’s time to read another Bart Ehrman book.
It’s kinda ironic that a Richard Carrier review causes me to buy a Bart Ehrman book, but then I didn’t discover Vridar and all the other informative blogs it links to until I spotted someone slagging it off on Bart’s blog.
As to my position, I am entirely agnostic on historicity. I lean ever so slightly toward historicity but I’ve seem most of the arguments disposed of, so I’m not holding out much hope for the arguments I still think have some validity.
I concurred with all your points then, and now even more so on subsequent reflection. Ehrman is under pressure from his family, from his colleagues, from his career, and even his own risk of self-embarrassment, to avoid “teetering” where the evidence actually leads. But that all only piles on top of a more universal problem facing scholars in Jesus studies.
All scholars, in all fields, but especially the humanities (where evidence and conclusions are much more subjective and squishy, and methodology much less well-vetted or spelled-out) have a tendency (per Kuhn) to resist anything that challenges their wisdom, their colleagues, their entire publication history, and the core assumptions of their field, even their reason for getting into it. They will rationalize their way out of the ensuing cognitive dissonance with every irrational and unscholarly device, leading to an entire backwash of refusals to even read the evidence and arguments they are supposed to be addressing and yet concluding they’ve dispatched them.
For example, Fernando Bermejo-Rubio (whose views I have addressed here but even more head-on now in Jesus from Outer Space) is so invested in his own fringe theory that Jesus was a militaristic zealot, that he only rationalizes his way to that conclusion, he never does anything consisting of logically sound scholarship to prove it (which would lead to discovering his thesis is untenable even if Jesus existed). This is what most historicists are doing: they have their own pet theories they are obsessed with and have staked their careers on; and those theories require Jesus to have existed (as per the recent example of Dennis MacDonald; and of course the whole parallel example of the zombie Q-source theory). Ergo, they rationalize; they construct apologetics; they don’t do history like the rest of historians in other academic fields do.
Meanwhile, the other two thirds of scholars in Jesus studies have to defend the historicity of Jesus for the survival of their very faith. Indeed, half or more have signed contracts that would immediately result in their being fired if they were to concede even an inch on this point (the fates of Thompson, Brodie, Lüdemann, even Licona, for daring to cross that faith line even an inch keeps that lesson eternally salient: see the survey of examples in Fitzgerald’s Mything in Action). They need Jesus to be real for the most existentially urgent of reasons. Their academic freedom is nil; professionally and psychologically. By contrasts, atheists have no need of Jesus to be wholly a myth; we’re quite content with the standard mainstream thesis that he was just an ordinary guy later mythologized.
Just finished reading your brilliant book OHJ, and note that you cite Ehrman a few times. Given this review and your previous one on Ehrman’s egregious errors of fact and sometimes logic, which of his books do you recommend as decent reading (reliable on not only the scholarship he cites but his own views)?
I’ve told Bart before, John 18:36 dismisses his contention that Jesus said he would come to start a kingdom ON EARTH, but he persists in telling his readers that is what he said.
A bit of pedantry here: you describe Ehrman as “towing the Christian party line”, but – unless he actually pulls a barge along with a rope from a canalside path – you should call him “toeing” that line.
From my (amateurish and unsystematic) reading, the allusion goes back to the good ol’ days when boxers fought on sand rather than canvas: the referee would scratch a line across the middle of the ring which the contestants could not cross until he blew the whistle or otherwise officially started the bout. Thus, someone staying within the rules would bring his feet up to “toe” that line, but go no further.
As for Paul and his Christology: he argued repeatedly against “false teachers” and “false teachings”, but how can you conclude that he never knew of any particular idea simply because he did not take time to refute it in his (surviving) writings?
Oh good catch! Fixed.
Re: “how can you conclude that he never knew of any particular idea simply because he did not take time to refute it in his (surviving) writings?”
That isn’t quite how I argue. They are the ones who need evidence to get the probability up. All I have to point out is that we have no evidence.
Thus, in OHJ, I don’t down the probability because Paul did not take the time to refute every competing gospel. I down the probability because he should have had to interact with at least one of them that necessitates discussing the historical Jesus. For not even one to come up is improbable (not impossible: improbable). I explain the mathematical logic of this in note 13, pp. 518-19.
As for Ehrman’s mention of the angel Christology in Galatians 4:14, are there other supporting verses with the same grammatical structure other than 1 Corinthians 3:1 and 2 Cor. 2:17? It is indeed intriguing to see this grammatical structure corroborated in those verses but I’m curious if there’s anything else you like to add to that argument from Ehrman? Cheers!
No, I don’t have anything to add that isn’t already in the scholarship he cites.
In this article you had mentioned that there were six independent sources for the Nativity narratives. What are those sources? Are they truly believed to be independent by most mainstream scholars? Thanks for the info Richard!
From my review of his DJE:
Note that this is according to Ehrman’s methodology, where if we have an account that differs from another, the differences must come from a third source and therefore counts as an independent source. I do not agree that that methodology is sound. That’s my point. His method leads to absurd conclusions like this.
I haven’t looked into those other sources (other than Matt. and Luke). Is it the case that those other sources are much later and can’t be shown to be independent of the gospels, and thus Matthew is really the only likely source that the other five were (most likely) dependent on?
I think you are confusing common sense with Ehrman’s method. Ehrman says that if a source has new material in it, that new material is an independent source. Even if the document was influenced by previous sources.
Of course, Ehrman contradicts himself by also saying new material is an embellishment that has no source.
He just chooses which rule to apply as suits his needs at the time.
What I am doing is showing the absurdity of his first rule (which he uses to prove new material found in Matthew and Luke is an independent source, even independent of Q!). By applying it to the nativity stories.
Yes, the results are stupid.
That’s my point.
Thanks for the clarification. Yeah, I realize that Ehrman has erred in his methodology, and I appreciate that you stick to your guns and do what a reasonable historian should do, including applying Bayesian reasoning to these questions. I mainly asked because I wanted to make sure there wasn’t something I was missing in all this, since you said in this post “Obviously the nativity narratives do not go back to Jesus, for instance, no matter how many independent sources we have for them (there are indeed at least six).”
Cheers Richard!
Thanks for spelling out what those sources were. Clearly Ehrman’s methodology is fallacious. Has he ever said explicitly how he arrived at his method for determining independence?
“invented or borrowed ones to get their new family tradition started, but that’s no different from Ellis Island names today.” — There’s a good set of reasons to suppose the Ellis Island naming myths are myths.
http://www.nypl.org/blog/2013/07/02/name-changes-ellis-island
Myth busted!
“Ehrman also argues this served as a competing Jewish claim against the claims to divinity of the pagan Emperor …”
Did he specify which ‘pagan Emperor’?
He doesn’t. But neither would I expect him to. The formulation of the concept can’t be dated precisely enough to be sure of any one answer. I think Ehrman just imagines it as a challenge to the position itself, not to any specific holder of it.
Cheers, though some 1st & 2nd century Emperors backed pagan divine beings: Ptolemy Soter’s Serapis persisted for a quite a while – even Vespasian and Hadrian were followers (Hadrian had a serapium in his Rome villa).
Taylor, R. (2004). Hadrian’s Serapeum in Rome. American Journal of Archaeology, 108(2), 223-266.
Thanks. This is a very well-written and informative review. I keep rereading it to learn different things and to understand nuanced points. Keep up the good work. Indeed the historicity thesis is crumbling.
“Ehrman also does not examine Eastern Orthodox, Coptic, Ethiopian, or Nestorian or Assyrian Christianity, for example. They did not necessarily follow the Nicene creed”
Are you sure about this, Richard? I’ve always heard that all of the above endorse the Nicene creed. The Eastern Orthodox, Coptic and Ethiopian churches (monophysite) and the (Assyrian) Church of the East (duophysite or Nestorian) supposedly split from orthodoxy only at the council of Chalcedon.
Am I completely off on this?
It’s complicated.
For example, the Nestorians by definition maintain a dual nature creed that is anti-Nicene. They did not exist when the Nicene creed was decided. Nestorius thought the Nicene creed was screwy, a hundred years after Nicea, and thus went churches on his side. It was the fact that these churches agreed with Nestorius against the Nicene creed that necessitated the subsequent councils to get them kicked out. And so they were. Nestorians were officially declared heretical in Ephesus in 431 and even more forcefully at Chalcedon in 451. At no time was there a distinctly Nestorian church that adopted the Nicene creed.
Each of those other churches likewise has some weird but not identical story that doesn’t fit the kumbaya picture of “it’s Nicene creeds all the way down, everyone agrees.”
As a very different example, the Eastern Orthodox church was and is all about the Nicene Creed, but very quickly (maybe a century or two) the West introduced the filioque modification as if it had always been in the creed. The Orthodoxists rebelled. This rebellion only resulted in an official schism many centuries later, but the de facto creedal schism actually dates all the way back to the early Middle Ages. And the question is so nitpickingly trivial, it’s one of the great questions why such an irrelevant triviality eternally fractured the entire church across the world.
So no, you’re not wrong. But there is still something here to explain.
Thanks for the clarification. I had no idea about the anti-nicene stance of the Nestorians.
BTW, I thought in the original passage you meant the non-chalcedonian Oriental Church, not the chalcedonian Eastern Orthodox Church, which is why I included it with the monophysites. My mistake.
Thank you for this detailed, review, Dr. Carrier. I recently finished reading this book, so your comments were very helpful. Trying to follow biblical scholarship as a layperson is quite difficult (as you can imagine). First I have to separate the apologists from the more or less neutral scholars and then try to ascertain which ideas are relatively well accepted and supported (the consensus view) and which are more towards the fringe (or cutting edge, depending on one’s point of view, I suppose). With limited reading in the field I feel sometimes like I am just feeding my confirmation bias, but at least I try for intellectual honesty. Along this line, there was one thing that caught my eye in your review that I would appreciate some more information on.
You mentioned that the consensus about the “Q” source (I realize that is redundant!) is changing. I was introduced to Q many years ago in a college course I took on Judeo-Christian Heritage, so it has a long history as a hypothesis. What has happened to the hypothesis and what would you recommend I read for more information?
Thanks!
See OHJ, pp. 269-70, w. nn. 33-34, for the rising tide, which once again “the consensus” is just ignoring.
Mark Goodacre argued against Q http://www.markgoodacre.org/Q/ (and still does)
What do you think about Ehrman’s position that convicts executed by crucifixion would not, as a rule, be allowed to be buried, and would rot on the cross? It was one of the most polemic aspects of his book, and I’d be especially interested in knowing your opinion, since you’re a qualified classicist.
As I explain in the article above: that was not the practice in Judea, where a special imperial decree applied. We have historical (Joephus), legal (Mishnah), eyewitness (Philo), and archaeological (Yehohanan) verification of that being the case. Ehrman ignores or gets wrong all four pieces of evidence.
The last should be obvious (were Ehrman’s claim true, we could not have found the ankle of Yehohanan in an ossuary). The rest are documented and explained in my chapter on burial in The Empty Tomb (although several other experts have been tearing him up on this as well: from Craig Evans to Jodi Magness).
Craig has tried to answer these arguments on his blog, but not very well.
Dr. Carrier.. I haven’t read this book.. but one thing that struck was that Ehrman seems to think that Romulus was a historical figure. I don’t know if he says that explicitly in the book, but he kind of implied it in a recent interview. He said something like, “Some were great kings like Romulus that were later divinized.” My impression was that Romulus’ story was filled with such extraordinary biographical events that it was an obvious etiological myth and unlikely to be based on the life of a historical individual. I guess the logic behind that conclusion would be something like Law’s principle of contamination. Is this right about Ehrman’s position and do you have any comments on the soundness of his assumption here? If he does think that Romulus was historical, I suppose that would color his prior probability assumptions about the historicity of Jesus. Thanks
Ehrman can be excused for not knowing ancient Roman history. He was never trained in it. If he had read my book On the Historicity of Jesus he would have been corrected on this, as I even cite the scholarship pertaining to the point (Romulus is in the subject index). There’s no evidence Romulus was even an idea until the 4th century BC. He was then retrodicted into Roman history four centuries earlier, using a story adapted from a Greek myth about a completely different set of twins, possibly in order to explain (and Romanize) the origins of the old war god Quirinus, with whom he was equated, a deity the Romans borrowed from the Sabines.
Basically, when you subtract everything said of Romulus that comes from somewhere else, or can be shown to have been embellished on top of earlier tales, or (like you say) is so absurd as to be self-evidently ahistorical, there isn’t anything else left that has any credibility as historical.
“Daniel 9, which actually does have the word messiah in it, and actually does say the messiah would die (and, incidentally, also gives a mathematical prediction as to when this would happen that on the simplest calculation gives us the era of Pontius Pilate)”
Then why do you suppose that the first Christians “saw” Jesus in Daniel 9 as you claim in this video? https://youtu.be/79Lmmy2jfeo (at 7:20)
Doesn’t the never-been-to-earth-celestial-Jesus theory argue that the first Christians believed Jesus had died before humanity and earth were created?
Thanks for this interesting book review!
I don’t know where you get the idea of Daniel 9 talking about a messiah who “had died before humanity and earth were created.” Daniel 9 is talking about the future, not the past. Or any other text saying that. For myself, I have seen nothing that speaks of a messiah who died at the dawn of creation.
Pointing out that there was a hierarchy of celestial beings in temple era Judaism is an important part of the puzzle. As with many elements of theology, whether they are called gods or angels is actually superficial. But the priests will argue the difference at immense length.
The idea of one fixed canon of scripture that is rigorously controlled is probably a late development resulting from Constantine’s takeover of the Christian church. It is a project that can only succeed when backed by state power. The Pentateuch emerged much earlier of course, but only a few years after it is being added to again. Constantine is embracing Christianity for political reasons which require a standard canon that is purged of all material that could threaten the state. And as the first half of the material is taken from Judaism, the surviving Judaic cults have to adopt an approved canon as well.
We should not expect any work that conflicts with the narrative Constantine is attempting to produce to survive. Given the central role of the Messiah in Judaism, it is remarkable how infrequently he appears in the Torah.
The boundaries between religious works, fiction and non-fiction were clearly very porous and different sects would make different selections and these would change over time. One of the major tells that Judaism was originally a product of the Babylonian exile is the fact that Moses is raised to the position of most important prophet. The new is syncretic, fusing Judean pagan worship with Persian Zoroastrianism. And this makes them the ideal folk to install as a new ruling elite when Cyrus the Great, a Persian takes over.
The promise of a new Moses to take the exiles back would surely be a part of the new religion. And half a millennia later, Mark is very conspicuously producing a ‘super Moses’ with ten miracles to Moses’ five.
We don’t know the point at which Jesus the God is invented, but it certainly does not require a historical Jesus. There was never a need for a historical Gabriel or Hercules.
One question about Ehrman’s example of Apollonius of Tyana: He cites this example of a man who was CLEARLY historical but then mythologized after his death. My question would be, how is the evidence for Apollonius different (better? worse?) than the evidence for Jesus? Are historians committed to the position that he was a historical person, or would it be reasonable to doubt that as well?
First, Apollonius experts are not so sure Apollonius existed, and none would be shocked by the suggestion he didn’t. It would be regarded as a viable theory, and probably one hard to rule out.
Second, Apollonius doesn’t belong to a high-myth reference class (he isn’t a worshipped savior deity, and doesn’t score high enough on the Rank-Raglan scale or any other high-myth-content scale, so far as I know).
Third, Apollonius wasn’t the savior deity of the victorious medieval culture that decided what evidence to preserve, so survival of evidence for him is expected to be much lower than for Jesus.
Fourth, Apollonius has what Jesus doesn’t: described eyewitness source documents (Philostratus tells us what eyewitness sources he used and describes and names them), his own writings (Philostratus includes letters written by Apollonius), and a second generation corroboration of historicity (Lucian reports that Alexander of Abonuteichos, whom Lucian knew personally, was a disciple of Apollonius, which is akin to if Paul said Cephas was a disciple taught by Jesus).
However, (a) the letters by Apollonius are literarily suspect and probably fake, and (b) inventing named sources was common in mythography (as Alan Cameron proves, whom I cite on the point on On the Historicity of Jesus). So the evidence for Apollonius’s historicity, though still better than for Jesus, is actually somewhat weak and inconclusive.
The one piece that seems strongest is Lucian’s remarks, as it is unlikely Lucian could have believed what he says if Apollonius didn’t exist. Although one problem with it is timeline: it does not seem plausible that Apollonius, said to have died in the 90s AD, could have had disciples still alive by the 160s AD. So the historicity of Apollonius requires assuming Philostratus grossly erred in dating him, which requires concluding his named sources are indeed fake.
On the other hand, we don’t have early evidence that lacks a historical Apollonius but depicts him as a celestial revealed being, as Paul’s letters do for Jesus. We also lack telltale evidence of ahistoricity for Apollonius such as we have for Jesus in Acts, as I describe in chapter 9 of OHJ.
“Why did Christian “orthodoxists” so desperately need to affirm only “one” God, and why at the same time insist Jesus and the Holy Spirit were the same exact thing as that one God? What was so repugnant, or dangerous, or destructive of their other beliefs, in the notion of just embracing three deities, or simply saying Jesus was an archangel doing God’s will, as Paul was teaching in the first place?”
You have your own hypothesis about this?
“Ehrman also finds evidence in Paul that explicitly states that Paul and his Christian congregations simply assumed without argument that Jesus was in fact an angel. He found this demonstrated by the grammatical analysis of Gal. 4:14 performed by several previous scholars (p. 250). I had not discovered that argument myself, and it is intriguing, supporting my case for that same conclusion in OHJ.”
Since this didn’t appear in your book, would it be worth writing an academic article in which you show how this research on Gal 4:14 is additional evidence for mythicism?
There is no reason to suppose, as Ehrman does, that Jesus was an apocalyptic prophet. Paul says “But Christ has indeed been raised from the dead, the firstfruits of those who have fallen asleep” (1 Cor 15:20). Paul is identifying that Jesus was the first fruits of the general resurrection of souls at the end of days, so the end times were imminent. Paul or one of the other first Christians could have learned this firstfruits business from something they thought was Jesus through hallucinations. And, Mark could have learned this apocalyptic stuff from Paul, and simply invented the apocalyptic material in his gospel. Therefore, there is no reason to suppose, as Ehrman does, that the historical Jesus, if there was one, was an apocalyptic prophet.
Correct. Paul also describes the apocalypse as being taught by Jesus in 1 Thess. 4:15-16, “we say unto you by the word of the Lord…” He just doesn’t say when that “word of the Lord” came to anyone…was it after Jesus died and “appeared” in visions to the Apostles? Paul only ever seems to know about the latter; never in his epistles does Paul ever mention Jesus ever saying anything to anyone before he died (not even in 1 Cor. 11:23, where Jesus is revealing a pre-death event in his life: it’s still being revealed in a post-death revelation). And that there was no distinction being made (between what he taught in life, and in visions after death) is highly peculiar…unless Jesus did not preach anything when alive. Which supports the notion that he wasn’t an earthly person at all, but only known through visions. But even a historicist has to admit, there is no evidence in Paul that whatever Jesus preached to the Apostles before he died, it had anything to do with the apocalypse. Paul seems to mean, they got his apocalyptic preaching only in visions after his death; just as we see happening still in Revelation (an entire apocalyptic preaching of Jesus…invented after he died, and portrayed as only being taught by him after he died).
So, really, the apocalyptic prophet thesis is really no better grounded than the Zealot thesis: both require “excusing away” passages to the contrary and cherry picking evidence and backfilling the thesis with a whole lot of suppositions not specifically in evidence.
I am using your excellent post, “Bart Ehrman On How Jesus Became God,” to annotate your corrections into my copy of Ehrman’s book. Re your reference to p. 232 in your point (1), I found the quotation on p. 233 last paragraph. Re your reference to p. 313 in point (3), I found the relevant section beginning on p. 316. Point (6) quotes Ehrman, but it would be helpful to know on what page that quote appears, so I could annotate my copy of Ehrman’s book with your correction. In point (8) sentence 1, it would be helpful to know on what page Ehrman wrote that. Point (11) sentence 1 refers to p. 355, but I could not find anything like that on p. 355. In point (12) Ehrman is quoted using “formidable” in assessing arguments for Q. but no page is cited.
Alas I rarely use print media anymore, so I can’t give you precise page numbers. I’m going off kindle, and had to check pagination using the Amazon website, which is sometimes off from the print edition by a page either direction.
Also, I can’t tell which sentences in your comment are questions. So if I don’t answer a question you intended here, please re-ask it in follow-up.
Working backward:
Your query about point 12: “scholars have mounted formidable arguments” loc. 1413, Ch. 3.
Your query about point 11: “the emperor and Jesus—were the only two figures” loc. 5296, Epilogue.
Your query about points 6 and 8: you’ll have to search Amazon LookInside to get the page numbers. Point 8, search for “no respect for Jewish sensitivities” (loc. 2405). Point 6, search for “it is widely thought, for example, that the Gospel of John” (loc. 1413).
Amazing review Dr. Carrier! It ends on a cliffhanger however, do you have a theory as to why orthodoxy was so insistent on having only one divine being? Thanks!
As I point out in this review, Ehrman devotes a whole chapter on that question in this very book. The TL;DR is that it was ultimately a political committee decision and not anything to do with real religious concerns. Most Christians were not advocating Trinitarianism; it was a fabrication of the Nicene council.
What one means by “only one divine being” is really just semantic. For example, Judaism and Christianity both still believe in many divine beings (angels, demons, Satan; Saints, the Virgin Mary), and most actual Christians hold what are “officially” heretical views (e.g. countless Christians actually think of Jesus as a man whose body was possessed by God, or by the Holy Spirit acting as an agent of God, or as a subordinate created by God and sent to fulfill God’s will, or else don’t have any coherent notion of the matter at all but merely repeat vacuous shibboleths according to what they believe they are “required” to do). So there never really has been the kind of insistence on “one divine being” as Christian intellectual rhetoric has long obsessed over. It really has just come down to honor terminology (e.g. what divine beings “get” to be assigned the specific name “God,” which in such a role acts more as an honorific than an actual classifier).
So really the question is, “Why obsess over this semantic game?” One can only speculate, as delusional people are never honest even with themselves about their actual motives for such bizarre behavior, so we can’t “ask” them. My top speculation is that allowing anything else to be called God or believed as independently powerful and important as God opens the door to religious multiculturalism, i.e. it allows other religions a claim to possibly being “true.” Whereas if there is only “one” supreme God, the debate is entirely reframed as over whether you are worshiping the real one or not.
re: ““The idea that Jesus is God is not an invention of modern times…it was the view of the very earliest Christians soon after Jesus’s death” (p. 3). Because, “soon after Jesus’s death, the belief in his resurrection led some of his followers to say he was God” (p. 83)”…
re: “admitting the first Christians regarded Jesus to be a preexistent divine archangel lends unexpected support to mythicism.”
How does admitting that the first Christians regarded Jesus to be a preexistent divine archangel – AFTER his resurrection – lend unexpected support to mythicism?
Ehrman plainly says “AFTER Jesus’ death, the BELIEF IN HIS RESURRECTION led some of his followers to say he was God”.
This is a far cry different than saying there was some cult that ALREADY believed in a Celestial Jesus who had been crucified by demons, and later they learned, through some kind of “revelation” (hallucination? dream? “inspired” re-thinking of OT scriptures) had been “raised from the dead”. This “cult” believed, even before the “resurrection revelation”, that Jesus was a Celestial Being.
But, for someone to conclude AFTER a dead Jesus was “raised from the dead”, that the “risen Jesus” must have been pre-existent, maybe from the very beginning, and then “sent by God” to earth — that’s just a matter of trying to comprehend who this “Jesus”, who got raised from the dead, really was in the Big Picture.
Heck, I’m nowhere near being a Mythicist, but, I’ve long believed that “Christ” – “the Messiah” – was existent before the creation of the universe. But, that hardly means anything in favor of Mythicism.
Am I missing something here?
Remember, support does not mean proof. Just, support. As in: the thesis gets more probable when that is admitted than when it is not; but not necessarily more probable than alternatives (like historicist incarnationism, by far the most plausible alternative to cosmic mythicism). 10% is ten times more likely than 1%. But still nine times less likely than 90%. The probability of mythicism overall only comes from a congeries of evidence, not some single smoking gun.
But this is why it mattered that Ehrman used to deny my established background information (in chs. 4–6, and esp. Element 10) that the first Christians believed Jesus was a preexistent being made incarnate. The function of denying that is to make it less probable that Christians would ever at first think that, and therefore reduce the probability that they could conceive of a cosmically incarnated Christ at all.
This is basically a “they couldn’t have thought of that without a historical man” apologetic—similar to “they couldn’t imagine a crucified angel, so there had to be a guy,” which is untrue, because the ancients could imagine a crucified incarnated angel, and the location is then irrelevant; crucified is crucified, it matters not where; and same here, as to incarnated angel altogether: see Can Paul’s Human Jesus Not Be a Celestial Jesus? which is all about McGrath trying to use Ehrman’s previous (and now abandoned) argument to argue against mythicism in exactly this way (just as Ehrman did).
A similar use of this false datum is to argue “no Jew would believe a man was literally God, therefore Jesus had to have existed,” which is refuted by admitting that this is not what preexistent incarnationism holds (as it always maintains their belief is that he is a created agent of God, and not literally God, thus eliminating the objection). Hence my words: “This is exactly what I argued in Not the Impossible Faith, and which Ehrman once denounced as misinformed (DJE, p. 167). Yet now he admits I was entirely correct.”
But now that Ehrman has changed tunes (and without apology), agreeing with my already-well-evidenced background information that they imagined this all along, the argument above goes away. They could imagine it, and right away. The very people who even supposedly walked the Earth with him. Yet if even they could imagine him an incarnated space angel, then even more could anyone told this in revelations (whether dreams or visions) or finding it hidden in scripture. Ehrman is thus abandoning an argument against mythicism (it was never a good argument, but still).
So the probability of mythicism goes up now, by exactly the amount it would have gone down had that argument been sound and valid instead. I already factored this in in my study, so its probabilities are already there. They don’t increase. But that is because I disproved Ehrman’s argument with facts already. The only thing that has changed is that Ehrman now agrees that his argument has been disproved. This must logically then have the corresponding effect on anyone who had previously bought it.