The Civil Rights Act protects trans and gay people now. Because the Supreme Court has so ruled.

I’ve long said some of the best philosophy written is in Supreme Court rulings. It’s always practical, real-world philosophy, that actually affects lives, so it’s also often more important than much that passes for philosophy in academia. I think you can learn more about free will by carefully reading Supreme Court rulings on it than in whole philosophy books about it. And Roe v. Wade was a masterpiece in philosophical literature; it should be included in an anthology of most important publications in philosophy of the 20th century. If you haven’t read it, you should. You may be surprised to find it does not say what you think it does; and that it also says so much more than people give credit.

Not all Supreme Court rulings are like this. Many are turds of ideological sophistry. But every once and a while…

“Sex” and the Civil Rights Act

The latest Supreme Court ruling on discrimination based on sexual orientation and trans status, Bostock v. Clayton County, is another example. And yet it was written by Gorsuch—a conservative. That’s right, you have conservative justices to thank for this. Well, two. Roberts concurred. Those are the only two reasonable, and legitimately principled, conservatives on the Supreme Court today. Of course the new standard Evil Trio dissented (Kavanaugh, Alito, and Thomas; the former is the new boy, but the latter two have hardly ever said a wise word in their entire tenure). But not for any principled reason. Gorsuch’s case hinges on a semantic argument that is totally spot on, but that I had never put together before. Seeing it spelled out, it’s brilliant. And undeniably correct.

To understand why, let me summarize Gorsuch’s argument in a more directly philosophical way.

The Civil Rights Act of 1964 had “sex” added to the list of forbidden bases of discrimination, ironically because a white supremacist in Congress insisted it do, because no way was he going to let black people have more rights than white women (that was pretty much his reasoning). So how does that include sexual orientation and gender? Because discrimination on the latter basis logically entails discrimination on the former basis.

Assume we are the ones who have to interpret that law. And assume in doing so we shall take it to mean by “sex” biological sex, specifically chromosome type. That’s actually problematic because of AIS and other conditions that break the link between phenotype and genotype (not all biological men and women have the corresponding chromosome type: see my discussion in Attack of the Lycanthropic Transsexuals!), and XX and XY are not the only chromosome types humans can have (see When a Person Is Neither XX nor XY); but that isn’t relevant to what follows. Let’s just assume the law even outright literally said, for whatever reason, “on the basis of chromosome type” and not “sex.”

And therefore, correspondingly, assume “man” and “woman” hereafter also means solely that—even though no one ever knows or is allowed by medical privacy laws to know anyone’s chromosome type, so no discrimination based on one’s actual chromosome type even exists; only discrimination on presented or apparent type exists, which is actually gender and not sex. Hence sex discrimination is in practice actually only gender discrimination. But pretend we don’t know that for a moment. (The distinction, as general knowledge, largely post-dates the 1960s, though now is well-established scientific fact.)

If you accept a woman for a job who is sexually interested in men, but not a man who is sexually interested in men, you are (surprise!) not discriminating based on sexual interest. You can’t be. Because the sexual interest is identical in both cases. Which means you are actually discriminating based on biological sex. The thing you are actually offended by and punishing is “being a man” in that situation. That’s the only thing that is “different” and thus the only thing you are targeting with your discrimination. And equal rights means equal rights. You can’t punish men just for being men; and you aren’t punishing “being interested in men.” Because you are cool when women do that, so clearly that’s not the thing bothering you; it’s men doing that that does, so you are treating men unequally. Q.E.D.

Thus that 1964 Civil Rights law already protects being gay despite never mentioning being gay, and does so even if you define sex as biological sex. Indeed, even if you define it even more narrowly than that, as chromosome type…even though there are more than two of those, so available chromosome type is non-binary; as is genital expression, and hormone expression. Even naturally, without interventions; but then we have interventions. Biology, alas, does not conform to bigoted ideologies; it’s way messier and more confusing. But even if we grant the bigot’s false assumption that biological sex is strictly binary and always matches chromosome type, the conclusion still follows: you can’t punish a man simply for doing what a woman does; that’s punishing him for being a man. If he wasn’t a man, you wouldn’t be singling him out.

This same logic extends to being trans. It’s not that the Supreme Court has now chosen to redefine the word “sex” in that law as meaning “gender.” After all, no such intent could be imagined at the time the law was passed. The distinction between sex and gender was not widely known then; so the fact that the discrimination they were talking about was actually based on gender rather than sex was also unknown to that law’s authors. Though here their intention would operate to the same conclusion: they clearly meant to outlaw discrimination based on appearances, because that’s actually the only discrimination they really knew about. But that’s not what Gorsuch argues. Rather, Gorsuch’s reasoning is exactly the same as for sexual orientation: when you discriminate against a trans person, you are not discriminating against presentation (say, “wearing a dress,” or “wearing makeup,” or “calling yourself a man”), because that’s the same in both cases.

Whether we are talking about a biological man presenting as a woman (almost in essence the definition of being a transwoman—not quite, but close enough for the present purpose); or a biological woman presenting as a woman (almost in essence the definition of being a ciswoman—again not quite, but close enough); either way, the presentation is the same: dress, makeup, gender label—whatever it is the discriminator is “offended by” and keying on to discriminate. So in fact when you discriminate against a trans person, you are in fact discriminating based on their biological sex—in fact even their chromosome type (or at least so you believe, and belief establishes intent). The thing that offends you is not how they look or present; the thing that offends you is their biological sex. That it is a man doing that (or a woman). That’s it. It’s not the behavior; it’s which sex is doing it. And that has been against the law since 1964.

“Your behavior would be acceptable and protected if you were an XY but not if you are an XX” is by definition discriminating based on chromosome type. Thus even a reading of the word “sex” in the Civil Rights Act as “chromosome type” inescapably entails a prohibition on discrimination based on sexual orientation and gender. Because come down to it, that’s all anyone is discriminating against in either case. Again, at least as they think; no one ever really knows anyone’s chromosome type, so the discrimination is clearly not really based on that, but is only believed to be by the discriminators; but that’s irrelevant to the above analysis. No matter which way you read the word “sex” in the Civil Rights Act (the way bigots want, the way its ignorant authors mistakenly intended, or the way liberals wished), the conclusion always remains the same: discriminating based on trans for gay status is discrimination by “sex.”

As conservative justice Neil Gorsuch, the very author of this opinion, put it: “It doesn’t matter if other factors besides the plaintiff’s sex contributed to the decision…if changing the employee’s sex would have yielded a different choice by the employer—a statutory violation has occurred.” Precisely right. “Discrimination on the basis of homosexuality or transgender status requires an employer to intentionally treat individual employees differently because of their sex.” And that’s against the law. And it’s against the law even when reading that law as referring solely to biology with the term “sex”—as in fact the Supreme Court just ruled that it did, based on the accepted meaning of the word known to the law’s authors when they wrote it.

As Gorsuch describes and quotes from a lower court ruling:

At bottom, these cases involve no more than the straight-forward application of legal terms with plain and settled meanings. For an employer to discriminate against employees for being homosexual or transgender, the employer must intentionally discriminate against individual men and women in part because of sex. That has always been prohibited by Title VII’s plain terms—and that “should be the end of the analysis.”

Snap.

There is a lot else of interest in the full decision. As often is the case, for example, it ranges over a lot in the subject field of “philosophy of law,” not just the particular factual and interpretive issues central to the ruling. But I’ll focus on the latter. Because good philosophy is also found in great rebuttals. And this one has a lot of that.

“Bu’ Whaddabout…”

The opposition tried to argue that discriminating against trans and gay status doesn’t involve discrimination by sex, “But each of these arguments turns out only to repackage errors” already exposed by previous Courts. Likewise they tried the usual “There will be consequences!” and “That’s not what the authors intended!” Neither of which, Gorsuch points out, is legally valid. Indeed, the opposition posed numerous commonplace examples of “bullshit bigotry,” the kind of stupid arguments you run into all the time, which are designed to deny or evade reality, instead of admitting you’re a bigot and what you’re doing is illegal.

The first set of arguments included:

  • Semantic game-playing (“but the complainants don’t say we discriminated based on their sex in everyday conversations”), which Gorsuch calls out with decisive examples of the irrelevancy of that argument—which includes the principle I often call attention to, that you cannot change what a thing is by changing what you call it; and that due to logical entailments, what people actually mean by what they say is far more expansive than what you might narrowly insist their words mean simply because it suits you.
  • The “we didn’t mean to do it” argument, attempting to claim they “lacked intent” and thus can’t have broken the law (in short, “we didn’t know we were discriminating based on sex”). Which Gorsuch dispatches by calling their bluff (emphasis mine): “an employer who discriminates against homosexual or transgender employees necessarily and intentionally applies sex-based rules,” because “an employer that announces it will not employ anyone who is homosexual, for example, intends” thereby “to penalize male employees for being attracted to men and female employees for being attracted to women.” It’s inescapably about sex; if it wasn’t for your awareness of (or belief regarding) their biological sex, you wouldn’t have done it. So claiming lack of intent is bullshit. Gorsuch thus exposes the hidden, true basis of bigotry here: it’s really all about bigoted ideologies regarding sex and always has been.
  • “But what if we ask them to check a box ‘gay or trans’ and never know their actual sex?” the bigots ramblingly try to respond. “There is no way for an applicant to decide whether to check the homosexual or transgender box without considering sex,” Gorsuch replies. In other words, being sneaky about how you learn things about their biological sex does not allow you to discriminate on that basis. It’s still discriminating based on sex. Because sex is the only thing that differs when you check those boxes. Unlike, for instance, the boxes “do you like men” which tells you nothing about a person’s sex; or “do you identify as a woman,” likewise. Anything else conveys information about sex, enough to discriminate based on it.
  • “But Congress didn’t say ‘gay’ or ‘trans’ so they can’t be included!” To which Gorsuch, the adult in the room, admonishes them: “discrimination based on homosexuality or transgender status necessarily entails discrimination based on sex; the first cannot happen without the second,” so it doesn’t matter that they aren’t explicitly named—a logical entailment cannot be escaped (bigots, you might have noticed, always want to escape logical entailments). “Nor is there any such thing as a ‘canon of donut holes’,” Gorsuch reminds them, “in which Congress’s failure to speak directly to a specific case that falls within a more general statutory rule creates a tacit exception”; to the contrary, “when Congress chooses not to include any exceptions to a broad rule, courts apply the broad rule.” That’s the law. Always has been and always has to be. So their objection is just dumb; it would make a bizarre hash of our entire legal code.
  • “But Congress never fixed it and should have!” At which Gorsuch really bitch slaps them by quoting the King of Conservative Supreme Court Justices right back at them, Justice Antonin Scalia himself: “Arguments based on subsequent legislative history…should not be taken seriously, not even in a footnote.” Ouch. Granted, sometimes one should and does take legislative history into account, but not in the speculative way they argued, which requires psychic knowledge of the secret thoughts of legislators.

At this point the bigots tried the most convoluted argument ever:

Asking whether Mr. Bostock, a man attracted to other men, would have been fired had he been a woman—we don’t just change his sex. Along the way, we change his sexual orientation too (from homosexual to heterosexual). If the aim is to isolate whether a plaintiff ’s sex caused the dismissal, the employers stress, we must hold sexual orientation constant—meaning we need to change both his sex and the sex to which he is attracted. So for Mr. Bostock, the question should be whether he would’ve been fired if he were a woman attracted to women. And because his employer would have been as quick to fire a lesbian as it was a gay man, the employers conclude, no … violation has occurred.

To which Gorsuch responds, “While the explanation is new, the mistakes are the same.” He analyzes over several paragraphs why this is a bullshit argument, but really knocks it in the end with an analogy that exposes why an argument for even more sex discrimination can’t be an argument for the absence of sex discrimination—and this maneuver just made me laugh, because it’s a classic internet-style pwn:

When a qualified woman applies for a mechanic position and is denied, the “simple test” [of the Court] immediately spots the discrimination: A qualified man would have been given the job, so sex was a but-for cause of the employer’s refusal to hire. But like the employers before us today, this employer would say not so fast. By comparing the woman who applied to be a mechanic to a man who applied to be a mechanic, we’ve quietly changed two things: the applicant’s sex and her trait of failing to conform to 1950s gender roles. The “simple test” thus overlooks that it is really the applicant’s bucking of 1950s gender roles, not her sex, doing the work. So we need to hold that second trait constant: Instead of comparing the disappointed female applicant to a man who applied for the same position, the employer would say, we should compare her to a man who applied to be a secretary. And because that job seeker would be refused too, this must not be sex discrimination.

Bam. In other words, wink-wink, “I caught what you were doing there. Nice try, Mr. Bigot.”

All their statutory arguments were absurd. All are well dispatched (well beyond my overly brief summaries; really, it’s worth reading the whole text). So, “Ultimately,” Gorsuch turns, “the employers are forced to abandon the statutory text and precedent altogether and appeal to assumptions and policy.” Generally this new maneuver amounts to a “But that’s not what they intended!” style of argumentation. To which one need merely quote Gorsuch again:

This Court has explained many times over many years that, when the meaning of the statute’s terms is plain, our job is at an end. The people are entitled to rely on the law as written, without fearing that courts might disregard its plain terms based on some extratextual consideration.

If only the Supreme Court actually did that so consistently as he claims; but it is reassuring to hear Gorsuch affirm this principle—we’d be way the hell worse off if he didn’t. Laws must be interpreted as written, not through a lens of ideology that restricts its implications according to shifting fashions. If Congress wants to address shifting fashions, it can rewrite the law. Until it does so, the law is the law. It does not matter whether Congress foresaw everything that law would entail when faithfully enforced. “Judges are not free to overlook plain statutory commands on the strength of nothing more than suppositions about intentions or guesswork about expectations.” Gorsuch surveys a whole list of examples illustrating why this is the way it has to be, and is the way it has always been.

After all that, the Evil Trio’s dissents offer nothing against any of it but screeds and whinging; with appendices, a veritable word wall three times as long as the decision they are harrumphing; in which they have no new argument Gorsuch hadn’t already refuted. As is typical for bigots: ignore everything that was just said in refutation of you, and just keep repeating the same arguments that were just knocked down. Ignore reality. Defy logic. Rinse. Repeat.

Alito and Thomas even try citing the late Scalia against Gorsuch, in which they reveal a complete disregard of what actually just happened. “What” Gorsuch’s use of Scalia’s doctrine of textualism “actually represents is a theory of statutory interpretation that Justice Scalia excoriated—the theory that courts should ‘up-date’ old statutes so that they better reflect the current values of society.” At no point, anywhere, in Gorsuch’s 33-page ruling does he ever make such an argument. He never appeals to changing values as a basis for reinterpreting the law. His only reference to changing fashions is rather in the opposite direction: that the law cannot be reinterpreted to match changing fashions; Gorsuch himself says that would convert law into whim.

To the contrary, Gorsuch’s entire reasoning was completely value-free: it hinged solely on what the word “sex” actually meant to the lawmakers who put it in; and on the actual, objective facts of what discriminators are doing when they discriminate. Nothing more. In every case, but for one’s sex the same decision would not be made. Which is discrimination based on sex. Period. To which argument Thomas and Alito offer no actual rebuttal. They just repeat the same arguments already rebutted, often even ignoring all the counter-evidence Gorsuch adduced to their each and every point. Generally, their every argument pretends the Gorsuch ruling had “changed” the definition of sex (it did not) or that discrimination based on orientation or gender can “proceed” without targeting sex (it can’t). And that’s that.

Kavanaugh then adds his separate dissent, in which his principle argument is, without any apparent sense of irony, “Under the Constitution’s separation of powers, our role as judges is to interpret and follow the law as written, regardless of whether we like the result.” That’s basically Gorsuch’s entire rebuttal. Talk about an own goal. Kavanaugh has nothing really to offer either, except, again, just repeating arguments Gorsuch already refuted.

Contrary to Kavanaugh, Gorsuch used the “ordinary meaning” of “sex” and did establish that that ordinary meaning encompasses discrimination based on the specific behaviors in question (sexual interest, gender expression). In fact he showed it does so precisely because of the well-established but-for standard at law: but for sex, neither of those behaviors is being targeted. It is only because the behavior is engaged in by “the wrong sex” in the mind of the discriminator that they are discriminating at all; and that’s discriminating based on sex. You are allowing men to do things you won’t allow women; and vice versa.

Kavanaugh has no intelligible response to this point. Because, frankly, there isn’t one.

§

To comment use the Add Comment field at bottom, or click the Reply box next to (or the nearest one above) any comment. See Comments & Moderation Policy for standards and expectations.

Discover more from Richard Carrier Blogs

Subscribe now to keep reading and get access to the full archive.

Continue reading