After reviewing the new 2020 PhilPapers Survey, I can say none of my views have changed; while philosophy as a field has slowly crept more toward my views than not (see my previous article, The New 2020 PhilPapers Survey, which also covers my thoughts on some of the strange or interesting things this new survey found, and what’s different about this one compared to the last one in 2009). So if you want to know where I stand on the standard thirty questions of the original survey (all repeated in the new survey) see How I’d Answer the PhilPapers Survey, which I published as the new survey was being taken (but whose results had not yet been published).
This time they added ten more central questions to those thirty, and then sixty more questions on much more specific topics of moment. I’ll start with the ten new mains. Then I’ll more rapidly run through the sixty sub-q’s. To make things easier here I will only speak of the target faculty percentages and round all percentages down.
The Ten New Core Questions
- Aim of philosophy (which is most important?): wisdom, understanding, truth/knowledge, happiness, or goodness/justice?
(1) This is a stupid question, as revealed by the fact that effectively zero percent of philosophers were “against” any of these things being the aim of philosophy. So, in other words, everyone effectively answered “all of the above,” as would I (because they are all important, and there is no continuous sense in which any are “more” important; there isn’t any you could “sacrifice” for the others). So that’s pointless. We learn nothing from this. Maybe we can glean something from the way the “for” votes indicate what they think is “most” important…but by what metric? No idea; rendering this useless to us, because we still have no idea what these respondents are saying or thinking. Worse, the “winner” (at 55% of philosophers giving multiple answers and 29% of philosophers giving only one) is “understanding.” Okay. Vague much? This question and its responses contain almost zero information of any use to anyone. I have no idea what the surveyors were thinking here.
- Eating animals and animal products (is it permissible to eat animals and/or animal products in ordinary circumstances?): vegetarianism (no and yes), omnivorism (yes and yes), or veganism (no and no)?
(2) This is at least better-formulated as a question. And the answers are very interesting indeed: basically zero percent of philosophers are against omivorism. Sorry, vegetarians. This is a crushing defeat. You almost never see such sweeping and comprehensive agreement among philosophers on any subject of substance like this. To be fair, basically no one said vegetarianism or veganism were wrong; and roughly a quarter of philosophers accept (or even “lean” toward) vegetarianism (and a fifth or less, veganism), but that’s not the same thing. Because none of them said the alternative to all that is immoral or wrong, even these few philosophers aren’t saying veganism or vegetarianism are a moral imperative, but rather a merely acceptable position, a matter of personal choice. I concur.
- Experience machine (would you enter?): yes or no?
(3) I just answered this in its own article. In short, if we assume Robert Nozick (the contriver of this thought experiment) meant to describe a machine that doesn’t deceive us about what’s going on, and yet still produces the pleasures we seek (e.g. from human interaction and the like) as his description of the experiment requires, then I’d answer “Yes,” like 13% of other philosophers did, because this is simply asking whether we’d prefer to live in a simverse over the realverse. But if we assume Nozick meant to describe a machine that does deceive us (thus producing genuinely false pleasures), then I’d answer “No,” like 76% of other philosophers did. I suspect such a majority so answered because they indeed assumed Nozick was describing a deception scenario, even though there is no way to tell from the way the question is asked here, and Nozick’s own description is itself vague on the point.
- Footbridge (pushing man off bridge will save five on track below, what ought one do?): don’t push or push?
(4) This is a variant of the trolley problem generally, the original form of which they already included in the original main questions. Which I think is worth their having done, because one can answer differently to both variants. But what we really want to know is why someone answers differently; merely knowing whether they do or not doesn’t give us as much information. I of course already explained I would answer differently, and why (a duty of care exists in this variant that does not exist in the original, so I answer “Don’t push” here, but “Pull switch” there). When it comes to other philosophers, a fifth are for “push,” half are against, and a sixth or so are in various ways undecided; compared to 63% for “switch” (it was 66%) and 13% or so against (it was 7%), and the rest undecided. So it appears my answers here break the same way most philosophers do.
I am still worried though of a possible confounding effect of including this question here, precisely because one should answer it differently as most of us have done: one of the few ways that I noted last time that philosophical opinion changed away from my positions is in that fewer philosophers now choose to “throw the switch” in the original trolley problem (as I just showed by comparisons above), yet inclusion of the very different “push the man” variant may have influenced some respondents psychologically to change their answer to the traditional variant as well, to avoid appearing inconsistent—because they haven’t really thought the issues through. The small variance would indeed support this (only a few percent changed their answer, would could represent the few thinkers who are answering on the fly, without really having examined the matter).
(5) I already discussed this in detail last time. In short, it’s “all of the above.” Because this question is very poorly formulated. Insofar as one re-phrases the question to ask instead whether gender is “entirely” inherited (an even more specific category than it merely being “biological”) and invariant (e.g. “chromosome type dictates gender”), or not, my answer is “Not.” And my answer is no mere opinion; it follows the conclusions of well-established science.
Most of what we assign to “gender” is socio-cultural invention with no actual connection to biology at all; while some has at best a weak (and thus highly unpredictable) link to biology (men differ from other men more than from women, and vice versa, i.e. individuals vary on all metrics more than “genders” do, e.g. you can easily find women who are taller than most men, so we can’t really even predict that, and that’s one of a very few metrics that do have a biological link), and most of even that is mutable by choice (e.g. you can have surgery and HRT; and starting HRT at or before puberty is even more efficacious in matching biological outcomes). I found from analyzing the answer rates last time that fewer than 15% of philosophers reject this conclusion, which means most are on board with my position, and transphobic bigotry is low (though still high enough to be concerned about).
(6) Philosophers are evenly divided. Somewhere between a quarter and a third of philosophers answered either objective or subjective; while only a sixth or so that it was nonexistent. The rest were undecided in various ways (one or another form of “nonexistent” and “undecided” thus making up the remaining third or so). I can understand the confusion. Because a major problem in philosophy today is that no consistent definition of “objective” or “subjective” has been established in the field, so each philosopher can be expected to answer according to their own definition of these terms, leaving us uncertain what in fact they are telling us by voting one way or the other.
The most one can takeaway here is that almost no philosophers believe there is no meaning of life (somewhere around 15% or so), and a majority that life sufficiently has either a subjective or objective meaning. I concur. I do think one can show life has an objectively accessible meaning (see The Objective Value Cascade), insofar as it is provable that everyone always ought to prefer being alive to being dead, absent particular (contingent and not common) reasons otherwise. But this entails referencing the objective existence of subjective experiences, feelings, and preferences (see Objective Moral Facts). So whether one decides the meaning of life is “subjective” or “objective” depends on how one defines each term. If to be objective one must exclude any reference to subjective facts (which means excluding a lot of real, existent, natural and empirically provable facts), then the meaning of life is subjective. But if objective facts include the objectively-factual existence of subjective facts (e.g. individual people really do have feelings about things), then the meaning of life is either objective, or both objective and subjective.
The new survey allowed respondents to answer both, so I would have answered both—for I believe both components comprise any meaning in life. Around 4% of philosophers also so answered (including those who offered “write in” answers like “hybridism,” which even more precisely matches how I might describe my position). Predictably, a lot more atheists did not tick “objective” than theists; but quite a lot of atheists nevertheless did (almost half). Which significantly topples a stereotype.
- Philosophical methods (which methods are the most useful/important?): conceptual analysis, conceptual engineering, empirical philosophy, experimental philosophy, formal philosophy, intuition-based philosophy, linguistic philosophy, other.
(7) This was a horribly worded and useless question. I already covered their and my responses last time. In short, for me it’s “all of the above,” with an important asterisk over “intuition-based” (which is only usable for adducing hypotheses, not for verifying them).
- Philosophical progress (is there any?): a lot, a little, or none?
(8) I am gratified to see almost no philosophers answered “none” (3%). Almost all (86% or more) agreed philosophy makes either a little or a lot of progress. But it would be more useful to know in what ways they believe philosophy makes progress—or better yet, what they would list as top examples. Of course, what the difference is supposed to be between “a little” and “a lot” is unknown, so philosophers will each be answering differently based on their own arbitrary lines drawn between them, which limits the utility of this question as phrased. We still don’t really know what these philosophers are saying.
I don’t know which I’d answer because I, too, don’t know what the difference is supposed to be. What would constitute “a lot” of progress? Over what span of time? I’d say philosophy makes much slower progress than the sciences, and maybe even slower than the humanities (reckoning advances made in history and literary theory for example, and techniques of production and evaluation in all the arts, e.g. even dance is far more developed in knowledge, training, and techniques than a century ago). So maybe I’d have arbitrarily ticked “a little,” otherwise lacking any other way to express such an answer because I wasn’t given one (bad survey design). But a lot of folks might think my take on progress in philosophy is that it’s “a lot,” given the many examples I can adduce.
(9) I covered this last time. In short, like gender, it’s all of the above. And most philosophers pretty much agree (only 11% answered only biological; those would be predominately race realists, i.e. racists). Race keys on biological characteristics, but attaches to that a bunch of socio-cultural assumptions that aren’t biologically founded. An excellent representation of this point is W.E.B. Du Bois’s comment that (paraphrasing), “Before the Age of Exploration, there were no white people,” capturing the fact that there was no such thing as a white or black “race” until Early Modern slavers invented the idea, specifically to create a socio-biological dominance hierarchy between Europeans and Africans.
Before that you had Germans, Egyptians, French, Nubians, Portuguese, Ethiopians, Italians, Nigerians, etc. None were “white people” or “the white race,” nor black. And none of these categories then were so securely “biological” as “race” has since become, because culture (ethnicity, predominately language and customs) played a larger part in establishing one’s heritage or identity. Having family roots in a region down to three generations was often well enough to make you “one of us” almost anywhere, provided you spoke like a local, dressed like a local, worshiped like a local, and so on. Color was rarely relevant. You were far more likely to face prejudice for your religion (down even to specific sect), or for your professed or suspected political (or even family) ties, than your physical features.
At any rate, to see my thoughts on how “race” as a category at least contingently differs in popular conception now from gender, see Transracialism Is Either a Fraud or a Delusion in Precisely All the Ways Transgenderism Is Not.
(10) Why this is even a question is best understood in the context of “vagueness” being a fashionable topic lately (though it has ancient roots, e.g. the Sorites Paradox). Like most popular philosophy, I think almost all the hand-wringing over it is overblown. The attempt to say it is “only” epistemic, semantic, or metaphysical already illustrates everything wrong with contemporary philosophy. Forcing things into predetermined ruts that are supposed to never overlap, rather than acknowledging most things like this are complex and multifaceted, leads to tons of wasted ink (literal or virtual)—ironically in this case, considering it is vagueness itself we are now talking about. (For an example of what I mean though, see Open Letter to Academic Philosophy: All Your Moral Theories Are the Same.)
You can read my answer to all this here. Vagueness can be physical (the location of an electron), epistemic (the circumference of England when measuring to the nearest micron), or semantic (the circumference of England when measuring to the nearest kilometer). Semantic causes of vagueness arise from linguistic choice: e.g. you have to choose what you mean by “circumference of England” (to the nearest meter or the nearest kilometer or something else?) before you can answer the question. Epistemic causes of vagueness arise from the difficulty of determining the answer even after the matter of semantic precision is settled: e.g. measuring the circumference of England “to the nearest micrometer” runs into insurmountable problems that make the epistemic effort impossible or “fuzzy” (the coastline at that scale constantly changes with tides, waves, erosion, and human and instrument error), yet there still “is” a true answer on that definition, even if it changes every microsecond and is epistemically inaccessible.
Metaphysical causes of vagueness, by contrast, which I think should more properly just be called physical causes, are when even if we had an epistemic solution (like some space camera that can instantly measure the circumference of England down to the micrometer in a single snapshot) we still couldn’t settle the question. Right now possibly the only actual case examples of this are in quantum mechanics—and only on the assumption that there is no physical fact of the matter underlying this, i.e. that our measurement problems there aren’t just another issue of limited epistemic access. For instance, Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle (e.g. that you can never precisely now both the location and the momentum of a particle like an electron) has both an epistemic and a physical explanation. Epistemically, the problem is caused by the fact that the only way to know anything about an electron is to bounce something off of it, which changes its location and momentum. But metaphysically, one might say that the electron has no specific location or momentum until you force it into one, e.g. maybe electrons are a fuzz or fluid spread out over a place and only “snap to” a specific place in that fuzz when physically caused to by some interaction or interference. If that’s the case, then the location of electrons is metaphysically vague, and not just epistemically vague (like “the geographic location of a hurricane or democracy”).
So there is no single answer here. I would thus have answered all of the above—putting me, for example, in the 3% of philosophers who also answered all three, or the 10% who answered “accept a combination of views,” which means pretty much the same thing (and it’s not clear how much those groups overlapped). I suspect most philosophers hadn’t really studied this subject and thus had no informed answers to offer; so we get the ones who were honest about that (the 9% “agnostic/undecided,” a rather high rate indicating this is not a well-known or settled subject of analysis) and the ones who arrogantly assumed they could answer from the armchair (like probably the 15% who insisted all vagueness is only metaphysical, which IMO only an ignoramus could have answered here). The 15% who answered “only epistemic” might likewise include philosophers who don’t have a good sense of what the difference is between epistemic and semantic causes of a phenomenon, while the majority (42%), who answered “only semantic” might be assuming that all epistemic vagueness can be resolved with a suitable semantic precision, possibly because a lot of them only know the semantic cases (like the Sorites Paradox) and not the epistemic ones. I suspect only people facile with actual laboratory and field science would be well familiar with the ever-present nature, and causes, of measurement vagueness—and that they can’t be resolved with any cleverer semantics.
Similarly, from reading the literature, I get the definite impression that philosophers who insist all vagueness is ontological actually don’t understand the difference between there being no fact of the matter (a metaphysical problem), and our not having access to it (an epistemic problem), or our not being specific enough to know what is meant (a semantic problem). Like the “Donald is bald” conundrum, where he either is or isn’t depending on where you draw the line to qualify as “bald” (how much hair has to be missing and from where?). That is obviously a semantic problem (if the question is vague, then we just aren’t defining precisely what we mean by “bald,” and can resolve the matter by simply adopting a more precise definition). It can’t usually be an epistemic problem, because there is no such thing as hair invisible to modern instruments. And it certainly can’t be a metaphysical problem, because on any “precisified” definition of “bald” there is always a physical fact of the matter whether Donald is bald, whether we have epistemic access to it or not.
The Sixty New Micro-Questions
I am not confident most philosophers actually understood these questions, or understood the options all the same way, so I trust the survey response stats even less here due to poor question-and-options construction and the tendency in philosophy for no one to have a consistent definition for anything. The results are thus less informative than one might hope, since you can never be sure you know what a respondent thought the question was asking or what their selected answer was saying, much less whether they even studied the subject adequately to have a reliable or informed answer to give. So I won’t bother with that; I’ll just state my answers, insofar as each question is even intelligible enough to answer. First, I’ll cover the questions that warrant more than a brief comment; then I’ll finish with brief comments on all the questions remaining.
The Most Vexing Questions
The question Capital punishment: permissible or impermissible? is badly worded. My answer would be “Permissable, but rarely advisable,” which may be what many philosophers answering “Impermissable” meant. I don’t believe there is anything inherently universally wrong about killing certain criminals (as Hannibal Lecter put it, “Any sane society would either kill me or put me to some use,” and when the latter isn’t a viable option, the former remains); but there is no good epistemic way to do that reliably (the false conviction rate is unacceptably and unproductively high, while even the benefits of executing the genuinely guilty are measurably small), so in practice a community or state shouldn’t employ it. But this wasn’t offered as an available response in the survey.
The question Causation: nonexistent, counterfactual/difference-making, primitive, or process/production? I would answer with “Process/production.” I covered this before, when discussing their original question about Humean causation. I assume this was added because that one was too vague to get at what non-Humeans (or even Humeans!) actually believe. Causes obviously exist (as proved by there being an observed difference between their presence and absence), and they have to be more than merely “difference-making” (as that does not explain how or why they are difference-making), and everything reduces to matter-energy in space-time, so causation cannot be primitive but derivative (of those other things). That leaves process/production—certainly if we allow that to include all remaining possibilities, but even more so if we suspect causation is simply a description of a fixed geometry in the fourth dimension (as I do, being a B-theorist about time and an Aristotelian), and that even a purely ungoverned random causation entails a process/production explanation of its outcome.
The question Concepts: empiricism or nativism? I would answer with “Empiricism.” But this is strangely worded. Usually this debate concerns knowledge tout court, not “just” concepts. Limited to only concepts, it is quite scientifically obvious that nativism is false. No one is born already cognitively aware of any concept; we are only born with inclinations that aid us in picking up or developing concepts; e.g. we are born with intuitions and inclinations that make language easy to learn, but we are not born knowing any language, just as we are born with intuitions and inclinations that make walking easy to learn, but we are not born knowing how to walk (unlike many other mammals).
But we also know that some primitive “knowledge” of a sort (if by that we mean only information and not strictly “justified true belief”) is inborn, e.g. we are born knowing what colors look like, and what scents smell like, and all other qualia—that is not something we “learn” in the proper sense, although we don’t become “aware” of them until we experience them, which I suppose is a kind of empiricism. We might also be born knowing things that look like snakes and spiders can be dangerous, or with a sub-architecture of grammar. But we cannot have proper knowledge of any of these things until we empirically verify them in experience. Which can attenuate the inherited information, e.g. we will discover that not all snakes and spiders are dangerous, much less all things that look like them; while any inherited tendencies toward language-learning does not prevent our empirically learning or developing language skills wholly alien to them. And apart from being scant and limited and unreliably “justified” only by a long-term process of natural selection, this inherited “information” is still nowhere near conceptual knowledge. An inborn fear of spiders still would precede any developed concepts like “spider” or “dangerous” or even “fear,” much less what to do about it when such fear is experienced. (See Why Plantinga’s Tiger Is Pseudoscience.)
The question Environmental ethics: non-anthropocentric or anthropocentric? I would answer with Anthropocentric. The basic question being asked here is whether our management of the environment should adhere to human concerns or disregard them, e.g. should we help wolves just because wolves deserve their concerns to be heeded, and not because it benefits humans (even if only aesthetically) to have them thriving in certain ecosystems? I answer as I do because a properly non-anthropocentric approach is logically impossible: even the non-anthropocentrists are acting on their own human concerns; so the question becomes whether their idiosyncratic concerns should be universally adopted, and that’s where their argument gets into the weeds.
“I just like wolves” is not a sound basis for a community policy. And even if it became such (e.g. enough humans voted for it), this would just be another anthropocentric enterprise: humans helping wolves because it pleases humans to do so—which thus ultimately reduces to human aesthetics. The debate is often instead framed as between aesthetic goals (what we just “like” to do, what makes us happy or feel good) and material goals (human profit & welfare), but I see no distinction between those vis-a-vis “non-anthropocentric or anthropocentric.” Both are anthropocentric environmentalism, and every option between them entails “costs,” in resources or consequences. Hence the debate is really always just about budget management. Otherwise, any question like, “Do ants and trees just deserve to exist and do well?” always answers “No.” Such conclusions must instead always be derivative of the interests of the self-aware (see Should Science Be Experimenting on Animals?), because there is no logically possible way to get that conclusion other than by appealing to such interests (even if covertly).
The question Extended mind: no or yes? I find to be utterly useless, because it’s entirely and trivially semantic: pick your definition of “mind” and the answer changes. Which means we have no idea what anyone answering this question actually has reported to us, because we don’t know what definition of “mind” they were thinking of when they selected an option. So we have basically no usable information here. Accordingly I can’t answer this question either (other than “the question is too unclear to answer,” along with 3% of other philosophers) because I have no idea what they are asking—because they haven’t specified what they mean by “mind.”
As described at Wikipedia, for example, I would answer “yes,” because a very broad definition of “mind” is there being articulated, such as to include any physical information-storage medium that doesn’t even directly participate in constructing a conscious state. But that isn’t what most ordinary people (and even most philosophers in practice) mean by “mind,” which is, rather, one’s conscious operations and the machinery directly responsible for it. The information in the books in my library, for example, only participates in the construction of my mental states as mediated by my cognitive apparatus. My eyes, language centers, the active effort of physically consulting the book. Which are always a gateway “in between” the external world and my internal model of it. Hence my mind, as usually conceived, is what is on the other side of my eyes in that causal chain. It’s really that cognitive apparatus that’s sustaining my mind, not the books “outside” of all that, and all the way on the other side of even my eyes.
Moreover, my books are shared by anyone, and don’t port with me (they don’t go everywhere I go), and thus are not unique to me or even continuously a part of me, and thus are not properly the domain of “my” mind. Compare a situation where two human minds literally overlapped in their apparatus, as if by some sci-fi surgery, so that they literally did share experiences and thoughts and feelings—that would more properly be called an extended mind. There is a trivial sense in which “everything is a continuous whole,” but that is of no use when real distinctions need to be drawn (e.g. you can’t kill me or give me amnesia by destroying or stealing my books, nor can I have you convicted of murder or medical malpractice for doing so).
So I find the effort to defend “extended mind theory” rather like trying to argue that the Port of Boston is a part of my sailboat because I dock there and supply it from there. Yes, in a trivial sense “everything is a part of my boat.” But not in any sense that matters to any distinction we are usually attempting to make when we refer to “my boat,” like how many people it can hold or where it is or what it weighs or who I have the legal right to kick off of it. I also find similar conflation of different contexts when extended mind advocates try to equate embodied cognition with their idea of an extended mind. That I grow to feel my car as an extension of my body (complete with developed neural-reaction maps to the ways its tires react to pits and bumps in the road) does not make my car a part of my mind. It’s the other way around: my mind is modeling the car as an extension of my body the same way it is modeling my body; but my body is not my mind. It is just the chassis carrying my mind. That’s why losing half of our body does not “destroy” any component whatever of our mind, much less half of it. There is no point in destroying all these distinctions with overblown theories of “extended minds.” Confusing the core apparatus of a mind with its peripheral tools is simply not productive. So if that is what the survey is asking me to do, then my answer would instead be “No.”
The question Method in political philosophy (which do you prefer?): ideal theory or non-ideal theory? is vague as to what “prefer” means. Prefer to use in place of the other? Or as in more often than the other? Or as the basis for testable models but not for enacted policies? Can’t tell. I’d have to answer “both” or “unclear” or “alternative view.” I agree with John Rawls that ideal theory (imagining the “ideal” society in which everyone complies with its rules) is useful as a heuristic for exploring possibility-space, but that non-ideal theory is what must dictate actual policy. I am a political empiricist: enacted policy must be based on evidence regarding what actually works, and not on ideological frameworks—apart from accepting as the singular goal of politics the maintenance of a civil society. See, for example, Sic Semper Regulationes and That Luck Matters More Than Talent: A Strong Rationale for UBI, as well as Part VII, “Natural Politics,” of Sense and Goodness without God (pp. 367-408) in light of my changes of view since.
The question Other minds (for which groups are some members conscious?) included as options “adult humans, cats, fish, flies, worms, plants, particles, newborn babies, current AI systems, and future AI systems.” I discussed all the weird answers to this one last time. Badly worded as usual, it’s unclear what any respondent was thinking “conscious” meant for the purposes of answering the question, so we can’t really tell what they were answering. That makes the data here largely useless. But as I noted last time, I cannot fathom why anyone would have answered “plants” or “particles” (yet they did). Based on scientific facts regarding the computational systems and processes involved (and known to be required), I don’t think those, or even worms or flies, have anything approaching a meaningful sense of consciousness (by which I mean integrated information experience, measurable as phi); fish and some current AI systems might experience some of the most primitive of integrated qualia (a very low but still significant phi) but nothing even resembling a cat’s experiential life or comprehension, much less a person’s; newborn babies would register a phi somewhere in between cats and adult humans (and likely future AI systems), and is of course rapidly developing a higher phi daily. I go into much of this in my recent debate Should Science Be Experimenting on Animals?
The question about Time travel: metaphysically impossible or metaphysically possible? I’d have to answer “The question is too unclear to answer.” I’ll repeat here what I said last time: the answer depends on what one means by time travel. If we mean by that what most people want time travel to mean, then it’s “metaphysically impossible” (unless you are jumping to alternative universes and not moving around in the same one, as depicted in the film Source Code); but if you mean what it really is—antimatter is normal matter moving backwards in time—then it’s not only “metaphysically possible” but physically happens all the time, just only in a way that would never make for an interesting movie (despite implausibly trying: e.g. in Tenet, their thoughts would also go backwards, and thus “undo” their memories rather than build them, producing no net change in anything; in fact, you couldn’t tell the difference between your going forward or backwards in time: see Sense and Goodness without God, “Time and the Multiverse,” III.3.6, esp. pp. 92-93).
And for their question on the Foundations of mathematics: set-theoretic, formalism, constructivism/intuitionism, logicism, or structuralism? I have no definite opinion to relate, largely because “foundations” is vague. Mathematics can be constructed on many different foundations, because it is just a language, a semantic system, based on a logic, which logic can be anything suited to the purpose. There is thus no such thing as “the” foundation of mathematics, any more than there is such a thing as “the” language to translate all languages into. Hence you can base math on set theory a la Zermelo & Fraenkel (which is not even the only one), or on standard logic a la Russell & Whitehead, or on geometry a la Euclid & Archimedes, or on category theory, and so on. So this question just isn’t intelligible. What are they asking for? If they had instead framed it as regards the ontology of mathematics, I’d have a more definite way to answer: I’m an Aristotelian, which is close to what philosophers sometimes mean by nominalism which in this context is close to what philosophers sometimes mean by formalism, and even closer to what philosophers sometimes mean by structuralism, which is really just a subset of formalism (and yet they give these as opposed answers here, as per the usual bad design of this survey). I could thus have answered every possible foundation usable here (everything but intuitionism), or as “There is no fact of the matter,” if I assumed they were asking me to declare the foundation rather than all usable foundations.
All the Questions Remaining
- Abortion (first trimester, no special circumstances): permissible or impermissible? — Permissable. I covered the problem with the wording of this question last time.
- Aesthetic experience: sui generis, pleasure, or perception? — Pleasure and perception.
- Analysis of knowledge: other analysis, justified true belief, or no analysis? — Justified true belief. But only of the probability judgment, not the fact independently (we only really “know” probabilities, and only epistemic and not physical probabilities, i.e. “the probability that x given the information available to us at t“). Plus I allow “knowledge proper” to exclude “accidental knowledge” (and thus all Gettier Problems) if one finds that qualifier useful. Eeither of which position some philosophers might have categorized as “other analysis.”
- Arguments for theism (which argument is strongest?): design, cosmological, ontological, moral, or pragmatic? — All are hopelessly weak; but the “strongest” I would say is (cosmological) design, i.e. the fine-tuning problem. I discussed this also, and what other philosophers answered, last time.
- Belief or credence (which is more fundamental?): neither, credence, or belief? — Credence. Because belief arises once credence, i.e. “confidence,” exceeds a contextual threshold, and consists of nothing else (see Who Is an Atheist? and Bayesian Statistics vs. Bayesian Epistemology).
- Chinese room: doesn’t understand or understands? — Understands. This is a classic example of where philosophers tend to fail to actually carry out the experiment as described.
- Consciousness: functionalism, eliminativism, dualism, panpsychism, or identity theory? — I would answer both functionalism and identity theory (a distinction that doesn’t really exist on any complete analysis). Strange to see here that 7% of philosophers are panpsychists and 21% are dualists (those numbers should be way lower, even accounting for deluded Evangelical Christians), but it’s reassuring to see 33% are functionalists and 13% identity theorists (and 4% or so are eliminativists, but I suspect all such respondents are really functionalists or identity theorists who don’t know what words like “eliminate” mean), which together means nearly half of philosophers are on the right track.
- Continuum hypothesis (does it have a determinate truth-value?): indeterminate or determinate? — I have no opinion on this problem. I consider it something mathematicians have yet to resolve. It’s also pretty trivial as questions go. Nothing about your core beliefs or worldview is likely to be affected by the answer; nor your epistemology or ontology, or aesthetics or politics either.
- Cosmological fine-tuning (what explains it?): no fine-tuning, design, multiverse, or brute fact? — By the study design, I would tick every box except “design,” because every one of those is credible and possible on present evidence. In a better survey design, I would force-rank the answers in line with their epistemic probabilities: multiverse, no fine-tuning, brute fact.
- Gender categories: revise, preserve, or eliminate? — Revise, until we can eliminate.
- Grounds of intentionality: phenomenal, primitive, inferential, interpretational, or causal/teleological? — The options here have no consistent definitions across the literature, rendering this almost useless as a question. The best I can do is say that in my philosophy intentionality is causal-structural, insofar as it is a physical property of the computational systems that exhibit intentionality. See my discussion of Reppert’s Argument from Intentionality and my corresponding Theory of Intentionality.
- Hard problem of consciousness (is there one?): yes or no? — Yes.
- Human genetic engineering: impermissible or permissible? — Permissable (one just needs to be cautious and ethical in its application, same as any tech).
- Hume (what is his view?): skeptic or naturalist? — Both.
- Immortality (would you choose it?): yes or no? — Yes.
- Interlevel metaphysics (which is the most useful?): grounding, supervenience, identity, or realization? — This is a semantic trashpit of meaningless or inconsistently defined words that are all useless. So I “Accept an alternative view.” You might call it Aristotelianism. Which can be equated with any one of the named views, depending on whose version or definition of it you are using. See The Argument to the Ontological Whatsit and Why A Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism Is Probably True.
- Justification: infinitism, reliabilism, nonreliabilist foundationalism, or coherentism? — All of the above, except infinitism (the only answer that actually contradicts the others). Fundamentally I am a reliabilist (beliefs are justified by methods verified to be reliable), which entails coherentism, but I am also a foundationalist: all belief justification rests on a foundation of the undeniables of direct present experience, including the experience of memories and mathematical and logical relations, well prior to any possible determination of their “reliability.” See Epistemological End Game and Bayesian Statistics vs. Bayesian Epistemology.
- Kant (what is his view?): one world or two worlds? — I have no interest in what Kant thought about this, and accordingly have never looked into it. I thus answer “agnostic/undecided.”
- Law: legal non-positivism or legal positivism? — I’m a positivist, but only because I’m a historian. I think it’s stupid for philosophers to confuse legal facts (what laws actually happen to exist and will be enforced by respective courts) with legal fantasies (what we wish laws were, or whether the laws that exist are immoral or bad). These should not be conflated. Discussion of what the laws are should be distinct from discussion of what the laws should be. Likewise the question of whether to disobey an immoral law is a question of morality, not of law (unless a specific provision for that is encoded in the law that applies), hence even though the answer to that question will often be “Yes,” this will not be a matter “of law,” but a moral decision of the individual.
- Material composition: restrictivism, nihilism, or universalism? — Restrictivist. The SCQ challenge to which is answerable semantically the same way as any Sorites Paradox, e.g. the Eiffel Tower and the Pyramid of Giza are also in turn parts of another composition: the Earth. They are not interconnected, so there is no thing they alone compose together. But they are obviously parts of larger compositions, up to and including the universe or even multiverse. So which composition you talk about is a semantic choice: “Earth,” and you are including the tower and pyramid as components; most anything else, and you aren’t. The requisite condition of composition is “physically/causally interconnected in a relevant way,” and which “way” is “relevant” depends on what is being discussed (e.g. landmarks, hurricanes, democracies).
- Metaontology: anti-realism, deflationary realism, or heavyweight realism? — This question relates to a paper by David Chalmers in which almost everything he says is wrong. It’s some of the very worst philosophy in print. I reject every category named, as essentially bullshit he invented to straw-man everyone who disagreed with his own weirdo view (ontological anti-realism), which is most definitely false. Chalmers might describe my Aristotelian ontology as “heavyweight realism,” but as his description of that does not accurately describe my ontology, this would only set-up a “baggage fallacy” by equivocation. I reject his paradigm. As do nearly 1 in 5 other philosophers.
- Method in history of philosophy (which do you prefer?): contextual/historicist or analytic/rational reconstruction? — All of the above. But philosophers need to read more of the former.
- Mind uploading (brain replaced by digital emulation): survival or death? — Survival (see my discussion last time).
- Moral principles: moral particularism or moral generalism? — Both. Moral principles are adaptable heuristics, moral particulars worked out in advance for commonly encountered circumstances, and are obviously both necessary and useful (it would be inefficient to have to reinvent the wheel for every single decision you make in life), but are only usable when the conditions they are constructed for obtain; when conditions deviate pertinently, particularism must take over. See Your Own Moral Reasoning: Some Things to Consider.
- Morality: non-naturalism, constructivism, expressivism, naturalist realism, or error theory? — Naturalist realism.
- Normative concepts (which is most fundamental?): ought, reasons, value, or fit? — It’s unclear what “most fundamental” means here, but more importantly, I also don’t know how this vocabulary has been developed in the field in respect to this question. This is referencing a discussion I am not read up in. I am a hypothetical imperativist. Whatever answer that entails here would then apply. But as I don’t know what that is, my answer must for now be “agnostic/undecided.”
- Ought implies can: no or yes? — Yes. It is logically contradictory to say you ought to do something physically impossible. See my analysis of imperative language in my chapter on the subject in The End of Christianity.
- Philosophical knowledge (is there any?): none, a little, or a lot? — A lot. By any metric. (See my answer on “progress” above.)
- Plato (what is his view?): knowledge only of forms or knowledge also of concrete things? — This gets into the weeds of which and whose definition of “knowledge” is being applied, and the answer has no relevance to modern life and philosophy, so I don’t even care what the answer is. I’m going with “agnostic/undecided.”
- Politics: capitalism or socialism? — Both. I believe the ideal system is an equilibrium state of both systems as checks and balances against each other’s excesses, akin to a well-functioning ecosystem.
- Possible worlds: concrete, abstract, or nonexistent? — Assuming they mean what we think is the ontological status of all logically possible worlds, my answer is both “abstract” and “nonexistent,” and I’d also have ticked “alternative view,” because I deem possible worlds as potentially existent, as opposed to actually existent, a distinction I cover in my recent tear-down of Thomism.
- Practical reason: Kantian, Humean, or Aristotelian? — “Agnostic/undecided.” I don’t know what distinctions among these philosophers on the subject they intend us to be answering for.
- Principle of sufficient reason: false or true? — “Agnostic/undecided.” But I am skeptical. As apparently are most philosophers. I have never seen any evidence or demonstration that it is true, it’s being false is conceivable, and alternative principles could supersede it (such as contingent principles of causality emergent within a universe).
- Properties: transcendent universals, immanent universals, nonexistent, tropes, or classes? — Of these options, my view is Aristotelian, which is most in accord with “immanent universals.” As Wikipedia puts it, “universals really exist within particulars as particularised, and multiplied,” although Wikipedia goes on to incorrectly insist nominalism is a different position that denies the existence of universals, which isn’t correct: some nominalism does; some nominalism doesn’t, and the latter is consistent with immanent universals. See Why A Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism Is Probably True and Thomism: The Bogus Science.
- Propositional attitudes: representational, phenomenal, nonexistent, or dispositional? — Phenomenal; albeit in a fashion that also entails dispositionalism and quasi-representationalism (modeling theory). Hence I may not agree with every phenomenalist account of propositional attitudes (see the following question, and The Mind Is a Process Not an Object and What Does It Mean to Call Consciousness an Illusion?).
- Propositions: structured entities, nonexistent, acts, sets, or simple entities? — Structured entities. See Giving the Churchlands a Fairer Shake.
- Quantum mechanics: hidden-variables, epistemic, many-worlds, or collapse? — “Agnostic/undecided.” Though I suspect a hidden-variables or epistemic account are the most likely to emerge; whereas I think the many-worlds hypothesis, though possible, is the least likely, as it violates Ockham’s Razor and lacks all the qualities of a good explanation (e.g. it creates more unanswered questions than it answers).
- Race categories: revise, eliminate, or preserve? — Revise, until we can eliminate.
- Rational disagreement (can two people with the same evidence rationally disagree?): non-permissivism or permissivism? — Non-permissivism. All disagreement is a product of either unequal access to information, or one or the other party relying on fallacious reasoning. See my discussion of “disagreement” (index) in my book Proving History.
- Response to external-world skepticism (which is strongest?): semantic externalist, pragmatic, contextualist, dogmatist, abductive, or epistemic externalist? — This is another case where I am not up on the way the vocabulary has developed and is being used in this debate, so I’d have to answer “Agnostic/undecided.” My responses to external-world skepticism are probabilistic based on model complexity combined with lack of evidence (skepticism entails much more complicated explanations of observations than does realism, yet offers no evidence for them). Whatever that would be called, would be my answer here, if it’s even being listed.
- Semantic content (which expressions are context-dependent?): minimalism (no more than a few), radical contextualism (most or all), or moderate contextualism (intermediate)? — As best I can tell, my position is moderate contextualism (not everything, but a lot of things, derive their meaning from context).
- Sleeping beauty (woken once if heads, woken twice if tails, credence in heads on waking?): one-half or one-third? — “Agnostic/undecided.” The Sleeping Beauty Problem has not gained my attention much as it is not terribly important. If someone can come up with a real-world relevance to solving it I’ll spend more time on it. Until then it goes in the bin labeled “waste of time.”
- Spacetime: substantivalism or relationism? — It puts me at odds with the usual view of physicists today, but I am a proponent of spacetime substantivalism, not only because it has more metaphysical explanatory power than physicists attend to (e.g. see Superstring Theory as Metaphysical Atheism and The Argument to the Ontological Whatsit), but also because it has more physical explanatory power than physicists attend to (e.g. relationalism does not explain why there are only four open dimensions, three of space and one of time, rather than infinitely many or some random number or even some constantly changing number of them).
- Statue and lump: one thing or two things? — Both. The distinction is purely semantic. You simply choose what you shall mean by “things” and then it will follow whether you are speaking of two or only one. Just as “America” is “both” the continent “and” the nation, even though the continent has existed for much longer than the nation. Whether “America” is two things or one then simply depends on what you mean by the word: the continent (which geographically includes most of the nation), or only the nation (which does not encompass the entire history of the continent and includes things other than the continent). See my discussion of Demarcation Theory.
- Temporal ontology: presentism, growing block, or eternalism? — Eternalism.
- Theory of reference: causal, deflationary, or descriptive? — Some combination of these is true. These terms are not consistently defined across the literature, so it’s not easy to tell what we are supposed to take them to mean here. More bad study design. But you can find (again) a description of my theory of reference in my discussion of Reppert’s Argument from Intentionality and my corresponding Theory of Intentionality.
- True contradictions: possible but non-actual, impossible, or actual? — Impossible. If we mean by “true contradictions” what those words plainly mean (see my discussion of the Ontology of Logic).
- Units of selection: genes or organisms? — Both. As I explained last time.
- Values in science (is ideal scientific reasoning necessarily sensitive or insensitive to non-epistemic values?): necessarily value-laden, can be either, or necessarily value-free? — Necessarily value-laden—because any and all epistemology is (see Epistemological End Game). But this doesn’t have all the consequences philosophers usually wring their hands over (e.g. that scientific research must be constrained by ethics does not entail that it replaces truth with desire).
- Well-being: hedonism/experientialism, desire satisfaction, or objective list? — All of the above.
- Wittgenstein (which do you prefer?): early or late? — “Agnostic/undecided.” I genuinely have no opinion on this.
That concludes all the new survey questions.
I think (1) could be answered by virtue of some analytical approach that says “Philosophizing can do all these things usefully, but its primary core competency is…” I would say something like wisdom. I think a good contribution for philosophical thinking is a combination of emotional intelligence, discussing ideas and their framing, and basic analytical tools. Most everything else is done using philosophical approaches but should be done within discipline-specific tools of the sciences, history, psychology and social psychology, sociology and the social sciences, etc.
(5) is indeed shameful, and shows a total lack of consulting the actual sciences by the study designers (since they would then have been able to ask a more coherent question). Gender is obviously a topic that’s going through some pretty rapid evolution, but I don’t think you’ll court much controversy among sociologists if you argue that sex has a biological root of some significance but that that significance is clearly overwhelmingly overrun by how institutions behave, gender is an entirely different thing that bears a non-incidental relationship to sex but is still so distinct that a panoply of gender presentations and forms emerge, and that gender ideas then become viewed as fixed rather than specific and mutable cultural constructs. The problem with TERFs is that they are bigots, so they play between the extremist feminist position of abolishing gender (which sounds great until you think about what the hell it would even mean and how you would achieve that, even without some kind of coercive enforcement) and the extremist right-wing position of policing gender with the pretense that they are fighting on the other side of that debate (such that they are basically fighting to defend two separate and opposed castles in the motte-and-bailey, because that lets them play “tails I win, heads you lose”). But most other people with a remotely coherent and fact-based worldview can recognize that nothing is inherently harmful about lipstick or kilts or dresses.
(7) should have been a ranked question.
Same with (9) as with (5), only here the underlying genetic reality is even more irrelevant. Genetic variations matter in humans, obviously, but they don’t cluster simply.
I actually argue that capital punishment should be impermissible. My stance is that ethics are so complex that totally absolute statements should always be made with skepticism, and so I can acknowledge occasional exceptions, but I think it is wrong for a society (that has the resources to avoid it) to kill someone that is under their power.
I think the deep ecologists can be interpreted as pointing out that even our most benevolent understandings can sometimes be plagued by anthropocentrism that is misleading and we need to take a systemic understanding, trying to be a voice for nature as a system because it can’t be. In practice, though, that still means anthropocentric eco-management. Because the alternative is to stand up for nature writ large, and nature doesn’t care. Mass extinction is perfectly natural.
“Because the alternative is to stand up for nature writ large, and nature doesn’t care. Mass extinction is perfectly natural.”
That’s a good point I should also have mentioned. Taking a posture “as” something else often commits the fallacy of substituting your own wishes and values for the other’s. And here, nature is a horrific monster that doesn’t give a shit about anything really. So there is no actual way to “take its point of view,” without abandoning human morality altogether.
And in particular here, that includes, as you note, “mass extinction is normal and even necessary and desirable” from nature’s POV. Things aren’t supposed to last forever; least of all maladaptively. Which reminds us to mention the dichotomy is false anyway: humans are a part and consequence of nature. There is no objective difference between our CO2 pollution and the O2 pollution of photosynthesizing cells in the Great Oxidation Event. Least of all if you are going to disregard human interests.
So you just “can’t get there from here” as they say again. If we are going to argue anything is “bad” about our Great “Carbondioxidation” Event, then our argument can only appeal to how it affects human beings. Nature otherwise would just want us to kill everything and readapt into a new ecosystem as we already are doing, like she always did in the past. Only we can have a reason to want a different outcome than that.
I think it’s worse than that. It’s not just that nature is a blind, uncaring, thoughtless stakeholder: Even then it could have a general direction, or a clear stakeholder position one could abstract. But “nature” is a gestalt comprised of interests that necessarily compete. Any one species that fills a niche inherently crowds out some other species that could potentially emerge to fulfill that niche. Any choice that we make on behalf of nature is in fact only going to work for a subset of it… based on criteria we made up because nature can’t supply any. This to me is the fatal flaw of deep ecology: They’ve put themselves into a Kobayashi Maru of their own making.
It’s rather like Christian fundies with the Bible. They have to ignore that their approach is in fact an approach, one that makes assumptions (e.g. the Bible is taken to be one work rather than an anthology of mutual commentary), because the strength of their approach is exactly in the rhetorical position of accusing everyone else of just interpreting the text by “man’s” ideas… when in fact yeah, man, that is what everyone is doing, even you, because it’s impossible not to. Deep ecologists similarly can’t help but use interpretive and analytical strategies that only humans can adopt.
When I’ve talked to deep ecologists who are not motivated either by irrational misanthropy and/or an immense love of nature that clouds their critical thinking, what they usually can admit is that of course a post-Holocene world is fundamentally different from a pre-Holocene one just like the introduction of any new species changes the biosphere. Their concern is that using social ecological reasoning is still anthropomorphizing.
And, okay, yeah, maybe, but not only is it not clear that there isn’t a difference between anthropomorphic or even anthropocentric reasoning and reasoning that actually causes unjustifiable harm, but what’s the alternative? If we make a stewardship scheme that tries to restore the environment to as close as we could without us being there, not only is that politically potentially not very viable, but in any case that is a choice: What about the organisms that could emerge after our wake? If we were to agree to a mass extinction, that’s hardly restoring the balance of nature: Our harm will outlive us, and we’re really the only things that could fix our harm quickly (nature would fix it inevitably in the long term).
As we pointed out to Paul, it is possible to try to have “nature” at the table as a bargaining agent (with humans speaking for it because, well, we’re the only ones that can – even Dr. Seuss knew that) without imagining that humans don’t have any concerns or without still prioritizing human interests.
I do think that deep ecologists have shown that it is often useful to us to think as if we weren’t thinking… but that’s just a special model we’re running. The alternative isn’t possible.
And I still have yet to hear a response to Bookchin’s point, that our role in the ecosystem could be as stewards, because we have the unique species-specific ability to do so. The only difference there at that point is whether we treat the long-term needs of the ecosystem and harm-avoidance for sentient beings as a goal or not. But, as you point out, we will always be doing that, based on our own satisfaction states.
Should the fact of actively killing a person in the footbridge question change the calculus from pulling a lever in the standard trolley problem? I know inaction is still an action either way, and the outcome is the same, but should someone ever change their answer in either scenario?
Also, I find it hard to think about trolley problems as divorced from the real world. So, would I “act” to trade one life for five if I didn’t know any of the people? In real life, probably not, because the threat of liability and prosecution. If I flip a switch, I could be charged with murder. If I do nothing, I can’t. You could extend this to the “what if one was your wife/child”. In that case, I would always save my wife/child, not just because I literally value them nigh-infinitely more than strangers, but because legally I could claim self-defense for whichever action protected them.
There’s obviously another trolley problem there in how much punishment would I accept in order to choose the more moral option. And that gets messy pretty quick. How convicted am I that one options is definitely more moral than the other? Also, there are major problems that arise from long-term incarceration in the US. Does being convicted of murder completely ruin my life? Does it ruin my kids’ lives growing up without a father, my family member’s lives (thanks to the court of public opinion or harassment)?
Yes. You must be late to the party. I have already fully covered this in the linked article (Everything Is a Trolley Problem). The distinction is duty of care (it exists in the platform case, not in the standard case), and the differential social consequences (railworkers already accept it’s risky and are compensated for it for that very reason, else they wouldn’t do the work, whereas bystanders know it’s risky to be on tracks and avoid them for that very reason; whereas if people could be randomly killed in trolley stations, no one would use trolleys, destroying the social utility of even having them).
You also aren’t correct about the law. Negligence (not doing something) can also be a crime. So the psychological bias against positive action is not as codified into the law as you seem to think (and even if it were, that could just be more evidence of the bias, not for its validity).
As to complexifying the scenario by introducing other factors, like circles of responsibility (you owe a greater duty to people closer to you in the networks of your relationships than to people farther out), and long-term consequences, and so on, that could indeed change the decision matrix. That wasn’t polled. So I don’t address it here. I address it (briefly) in my linked article on Trolley Problems.
how about the ‘choice’ of the sentient being: the cat or the gurilla or the locust. I’d be they wouldn’t want to be et.
Phil papers seem out of touch.
eg
https://theconversation.com/what-philosophers-have-to-say-about-eating-meat-100444
The survey poll shows philosophers are not much behind that position. Alas. You are simply referencing an unpopular position.
And there is a good reason it’s unpopular.