It is common to just assume God is timeless and spaceless. But I aver that’s logically impossible.

You Have to Exist Somewhere to Exist at All

If God has no location, then by definition there is no location at which God exists. And if there is no location at which God exists, then by definition God exists nowhere. Which entails that God does not exist. Because the proposition “there is nowhere that God exists” is literally synonymous with “God does not exist.” Just as with anything else. If I tell you “there is nowhere that faeries exist” or “Plato’s Forms don’t exist anywhere,” you would correctly apprehend me to be saying faeries and Plato’s Forms simply don’t exist at all. If there is nowhere that you (or anything at all) can even conceptually go and be where God or faeries are, then God and faeries don’t exist. Yet being somewhere is what it means to be located in space. That particular space might have no extension (it might be a one dimensional point and thus have no radius or any other properties); but it must still exist.

Which means God needs a place to exist before he can exist at all. He cannot think up where to exist and then locate himself there. He cannot exist “nowhere” and still exist to work out where to exist, so as to exist (by analogy, that “lands us” in the same “nonsense” as “that God, before making himself able to make himself, makes himself,” Thomas Ward, Divine Ideas, p. 17). Whereas space does not need God to exist. Nor does it need a “place” to exist because it is a “place.” Space is self-locating, by definition. Space is therefore a more fundamental ground of all being than God. In terms of existential quantifiers, God existing but existing nowhere is akin to “There is an even number n by which n × n = 25,” which is false. Existing somewhere is simply a fundamental requirement of existing at all.

Since it is the case that from any intelligible definition of being, in order for anything to exist, it must exist somewhere, this requirement of existence is satisfied even if that somewhere is everywhere (like the universe itself, or even abstract objects, however you conceive of them, and whether you are thinking of numbers or more complex ideas: they do not exist “nowhere,” because they exist, as potentialities, everywhere), or some other space than ours (like, say, another plane of existence). Even your love for your wife exists at a location in space: your brain. And since existing nowhere is not existing, it cannot be that God has no location, or exists in no space. And since it is circularly impossible to be at a place to think up a place to exist when no place to be at exists, God cannot have created a place for himself to exist.

And no, you can’t defeat this conclusion by saying, “But I can imagine God existing nowhere,” because that statement will be literally false: to imagine anything at all, you have to use a brain, which has a location. It is logically impossible for you to imagine something without a location. You are always imagining things in a location. The converse is not the case, of course—that you can’t imagine something without a location does not itself prove a location is required to exist (it’s simply a product of you using a located computer to simulate things). But it is proved by tautology. Existing nowhere simply is what not existing means. If you look in every place something can exist, and it’s not in any of them, it doesn’t exist. To not exist anywhere and still exist is a contradiction in terms. Hence you are always putting God somewhere when you think of God existing at all.

Indeed, “omnipresence” as an attribute entails God is everywhere, and thus far from nowhere: on that theology, God exists at every point of space we know. I’m not the first to point this out. See, for example, Arcadi’s analysis in “God is Where God Acts: Reconceiving Divine Omnipresence” in Topoi and Buckareff’s study of “Divine Location” in Alternative Concepts of God. See also “God and Spacelessness” by Paul Helm (and even the reply of Ishtiyaque Haji, “God and Omnispatiality”); and Brian Davies’ famous article on the whole problem of God’s relationship to time in “A Timeless God” where he shows you can only coherently rescue God as timeless by denying he is a person! The same would hold for space (to not be “here,” you have to be, by definition, “somewhere else”). Ultimately, every attempt to get God to both have no location and still be real is illogical—it contradicts something else the theist needs to believe about God, or else leans on magic words with a perpetually equivocated meaning (like “transcendence”).

That kind of confidently asserted nonsense is par for the course for modern theism, though. Just think of the Christian obsession with still insisting the Trinity is logical, or that God can be made compatible with the world’s malignancy. They confidently assert these problems to have been solved when in fact they haven’t—their conceptions are simply illogical. Hence their confidence in what they say is a solution should not be mistaken for having any actual solution. The fact remains that God must have spatial location. “I just don’t believe that” is not a valid response, any more than it is a valid response to pointing out that the Nicene Trinity is logically impossible or that one’s God as just described is logically incompatible with observed malignancies. The only real solution to those problems is to abandon them (adopt a heretical resolution of the Trinity or redefine your god or his limitations). In respect to place, God must be located either everywhere or only some places and not others—or else no longer exist, or not yet exist, or never have existed (a point we’ll return to shortly). No other option is logically available.

Which is why this is not really a huge problem for theists. It only annoys them because they are emotionally attached to all their weird preconceptions—just as with the Trinity and Theodicy, which are easily solved by simply giving up on their weird formulas and accepting some “shocking” heresy or other. Hence a theist can easily solve the location problem by accepting God is omnilocated and thus a spatial being after all—or by simply declaring that God necessarily exists, and if that logically requires a place to exist (some dimensionless, propertyless point of hyperspace), then it necessarily exists along with him. Of course, the theist has no reason to believe God necessarily exists—whereas we do have reason to believe space necessarily exists. For example, it is logically impossible to have less than zero of something and still have nothing, so there must be at minimum a zero-point of space. But that’s still a point of space (it just has zero extension; but it is still a location). Negative space is just more space. Positive space is just more space. So the least amount of space you can have is zero space. But that defines a geometric point of space. It’s still a place to be. And that’s part of The Problem with Nothing.

You Have to Exist Sometime to Have Ever Existed at All

It gets to be a bigger problem for theists when we point out that to exist, something also has to exist at some time. If there is no time at which you exist, then by definition you never existed. And if you never exist, you don’t ever exist—by definition. It is therefore logically impossible for a God to be wholly “timeless.” God can be timeless in a less ambitious sense: if he is located at the first (and, until he acts to extend it, only) point of time, then it can still be the case that time has zero extension. Like that previously-imagined minimal space, time is then a geometric point: a location in time, but still no span of time has passed. God can thus “instantaneously” work out what to do at t=0 and “instantaneously” act to do it, like some amazing quantum computer that solves every problem the moment it is turned on. But it cannot be the case that God created time. Just as with space, he cannot exist at some time so as to work out that he needs to cause time to exist. Time has to already exist for there to be any time “when” God figured that out. God therefore needs time to exist—otherwise he never existed—not the other way around (see, for example, the Oxford analysis of R.T. Mullins, The End of the Timeless God).

Time is thus more fundamental than God. God needs time to exist to himself exist. But time does not need God to exist. Because it is again logically impossible to have less than zero of something and still have nothing. So there must always be at minimum a zero-point of time. But that’s still a point of time (it just has zero extension; but it is still a time, and hence a location in time). Negative time is just more time—an extension beyond zero. Positive time is just more time—an extension beyond zero in the other direction. So the least amount of time you can have is zero time. But that defines a geometric point of time. It’s still a time to be. And that’s also part of The Problem with Nothing.

In fact, any zero-point of space that necessarily exists must itself be located at some of time (whether a zero-point of time or not)—otherwise that space “never existed,” and thus didn’t and doesn’t exist. There has to be a “time when” there was zero space, otherwise there never was zero space (and there was, instead, always a nonzero quantity of space)—and no, it can’t be located before time, any more than you can be north of the north pole. Time, conversely, must exist somewhere to exist at all, and so it must always be co-located with some space, even if a dimensionless point of it. There could conceivably be multiple, even infinite, such zero-points of spacetime (unless you conclude that that constitutes more than zero things, and you are supposing that everything started with the least amount of things possible—and hence no unnecessary things). But there can never be a time without a space, nor a space without a time, nor any place or time when neither existed.

This is again solvable, and in the same way—if a dimensionless point of time must exist for God to exist, and God necessarily exists, then so would the time necessary for his existence. But he won’t have caused that to be, because it won’t have been contingent: the existence of time is then logically necessary; and so time, like space, is a necessary being. The extension of time can be contingent—so God can still be responsible for making there be any more time than just the zero-point of time he exists at—but time itself must exist apart from God; he can’t be responsible for it. Nor, of course, can God “predate” time (that is literally illogical, a direct self-contradiction, as already noted: it’s like being north of the north pole).

Once we admit that God cannot exist but for a spacetime allowing a where and when to exist, yet also admit that spacetime does not require a God to make it exist, we come to realize spacetime requires no God—but God requires a spacetime. Spacetime is therefore more fundamental than God (a problem I pointed out before to Edward Feser; indeed, again and again). If spacetime can exist independently of God, requiring nothing more fundamental than itself, then spacetime has the better claim to being the ground of all being than God. After all, like space, time does not need another time in which to be located—time is a time, and thus is itself a time when to be. Time exists at all times. And space exists in all places, at all times. And thus time is also self-locating, by definition; just like space. No “second” time need exist to establish when time exists, just as no “second” space need exist to establish where space exists.

What would cause a dimensionless point of spacetime to expand into an extended spacetime is then the Cosmological Problem, but atheists have as many solutions to that as theists. Just explore the cosmology category in my website’s drop-down menu; but have a start with, again, The Problem with Nothing, or for a scientific model, see What If We Reimagine ‘Nothing’ as a Field-State? And if you want a more proactive hypothesis, something to match the theist’s weird theory that God just “makes” things keep existing and have the properties they do, we can theorize just as easily (and with a stronger basis in logic and evidence) that spacetime itself does that (see Superstring Theory as Metaphysical Atheism). “But you don’t know that for sure” is no more an objection to that than to the theist’s even weirder theory it replaces. Ockham’s Razor resolves that dispute in our favor (see The Argument to the Ontological Whatsit and A Hidden Fallacy in the Fine Tuning Argument).

Conclusion

As I wrote before:

[Theists will say] God is a good candidate for the First Cause because he is “not essentially located in space or time.” [But] this is actually false. A thing has to be essentially located in space and time even to exist; otherwise, by definition, it never exists and exists nowhere, which is literally what it means to not exist. But what I think [they want] to say is that God does not have a specific location in spacetime (he exists everywhere at every time), which would be a contingent fact, and we need God to be a necessary fact. But a primordial or existential “nothing”-state satisfies this condition. It is no more “essentially located in space or time” than [their] God has to be. Insofar as there has to be a time when there was nothing, and nothing has to occupy a position different from or the same as any resulting something, it necessarily did. Just like [their] God.

And elsewhere (and again in a followup):

To exist, an entity requires there to be a place and time to exist. Otherwise it by definition never exists and exists nowhere. Thus all entities that exist are dependent on and thus subordinate to spacetime. Everything that exists, to exist, requires spacetime. But spacetime itself, to exist, requires nothing but itself. It does not require some extra place and time to exist. It is place and time. Spacetime is therefore the only conceivable thing that requires no further substrate for it to be. Nothing “extra” need exist for spacetime to exist. But something extra must always exist for anything else to exist. That something extra is [minimally] spacetime: a place and time to be.

So it should have been obvious that spacetime is the fundamental ground of all being. We need nothing else to explain existence. Because it needs nothing else to exist. All the “being” and “isness” that is and ever was and ever can be, boils down to nothing more than place and time: existing somewhere, at some time. Even what everything is ultimately made of, may well indeed be nothing other than spacetime, suitably twisted and knotted up into the geometries we mistake as atoms and photons. There is no evidence it’s not.

In short, to exist, God needs other things to exist—principally somewhere to exist, and some time when to exist, as well as a great deal else (a plethora of superpowers, a convenient commitment to a particular morality, a working mind without any material to hold it together). But spacetime does not need anything else to exist to exist. Nothing could exist but spacetime, and yet spacetime could still then exist. Everything else, to exist, requires adding things to that—but none of those things that would make for a God are logically necessary; whereas a mere spacetime, even a zero-point of it, already contains everything logically necessary for a spontaneous multiverse to inevitably expand from it.

It thus matters that God cannot be spaceless and timeless. Those are nonsensical properties for anything that exists. Because to be spaceless and timeless is literally what it means not to exist. And since God is therefore not needed for spacetime to exist, but rather spacetime has a much clearer basis to necessarily exist than something as bizarrely elaborate as a God, and since just “spacetime” existing can explain all the rest of existence, exactly as observed, the impossibility of God being timeless and spaceless tells against there being a God. It does not make God impossible; but it does make God too unnecessary to credit. The rest falls to the evidence. And that does not bode well for there being any God (see Ten Ways the World Would Be Different If God Existed and its converse exploration in Bayesian Counter-Apologetics).

The point of the Argument from Non-Locality, therefore, is not that it proves God does not exist, any more than finding logical contradictions in a particular conception of omnipotence does. One can always restore coherence to theism by simply abandoning a dumb position. For example, you can redefine omnipotence as “has all logically possible powers,” and thus avoid any “omnipotence entails contradictions” argument. Likewise with Nonlocality. I have shown various ways a theology can be retooled to rescue God from these findings, and keep him compatible with them. But what the argument does is reset the playing board: there are conceptions of God it rules out; and those conceptions are often resorted to in other arguments (such as the Kalam). And there are consequences of the argument that favor atheism: it is easier to conceive of a mindless spacetime as a necessary being, and as the ground of all being, than anything as contingently elaborate as an intelligent magical being with unexplained motivations and inexplicable abilities.

§

To comment use Add Comment field at bottom or click a Reply box next to a comment. See Comments & Moderation Policy.

Discover more from Richard Carrier Blogs

Subscribe now to keep reading and get access to the full archive.

Continue reading