Yesterday I dealt with Bernardo Kastrup’s weird Idealism. Today I have just a simple thought to offer on why the equally weird theology of Alvin Plantinga is fatally incoherent, building on two prior articles of mine: Is a Good God Logically Impossible?, where I analyze James Sterba’s book of that title (finding that in essentials it’s spot on, erring only on one point of semantic trivia), and How Not to Live in Zardoz, where I analyze what one might have thought was a completely different question (how we can live in simverses without getting trapped in a psychopathic hell). It turns out, these connect. And they connect in a particularly useful way for refuting Plantinga’s Free Will Defense of Evil (which is indifferent to what free will actually is, so I won’t digress on that here).

The Point about Strategy

Because human beings are universally irrational and often delusional, the truth is not inherently persuasive. It is easy to escape admitting the truth or its consequences. Indeed it gets easier the more copious or complicated that truth is, because there is “so much of it” that it is easy to just lazily dismiss it all, or straw man it, or “choose your adventure” and nitpick one thing and ignore the rest, and every other strategy people use to avoid any causal effect of learning the truth. Critical thinking is hard; and requires genuine commitment. People are lazy. And disinclined to commit to anything they find uncomfortable. So there is a strategic value to single-point arguments: they can be truths that are more effective at changing minds, not because they are comprehensive, but precisely because they are not. The art of persuasion is not the same thing as the art of telling the truth.

Hence having an incomplete but slam-dunk point is rhetorically and emotionally useful. And to illustrate what I mean, I’ll first start with an analogy. While we do need to know all the ways that biblical morality is flawed, toxic, or bankrupt, and we do need to know where moral facts really come from and what they really are, it is psychologically more persuasive if we can slam dunk the point with a single irrefutable example: slavery. This was an approach Matt Dillahunty developed, and it’s pretty effective. Imagine our world, and an alternative one identical in every way (every single way), but one: in that world, the Biblical God consistently condemns slavery (rather than consistently endorses and even occasionally commands it), complete with reasons why His People must never practice it and instead always morally condemn it. In which world is that God more moral? There is no honest way around the answer: the non-existent God is more moral. Which entails any existent God cannot be moral. Mic drop. You’re done.

Needless to say the cognitive dissonance that creates is literally painful. So Christians, thus cornered, and being trapped in a delusion, will resort to absurd and illogical defenses to try and keep believing their God isn’t evil (literally, a vile slavemaster who is utterly against basic human rights). The three most common approaches are to defend slavery as somehow actually moral (at which point the Christian has lost all moral ground and thereby advertised their religion to everyone as morally repugnant) or to change the subject with a tu quoque fallacy (which advertises to everyone that the Christian has no response to the point) or to ironically resort to moral relativism and claim God “couldn’t” preach any true morality to the ancient Israelites because they were too primitive then or the culture was different then—or whatever illogical excuse. Which directly contradicts their claim that the Bible contains true moral guidance, and thus they have just refuted their own religion. Ouch.

Of course, usually what atheists will point out is not that (even though that is a more decisive kill, destroying the inner logic of the entire religion), but that the excuse doesn’t even make sense: if God can insist (even under pain of death) that the Israelites follow such difficult and bizarre rules as not eating bacon or picking up sticks on Saturday, surely he can teach them slavery is wrong (with, indeed, the same ruthless insistence); moreover, ancient Israelites are no less intellectual humans than anyone else today, or in ancient China, who were more than able to accept and understand that slavery is wrong. If you can teach that to a baby today; you could teach it to a baby then. So the excuse doesn’t work, no matter which way you look at it. The fatal weakness of this excuse is thus, again, a self-defeat, advertising to all watching that Christianity is internally incoherent—and cannot get its God out of being evil (even as a fictional character).

Yes, desperate Christians can try every rabbit hole here. For example, they can try digging in on the tu quoque argument and insist atheists can’t make moral judgments, etc. But that Christians have to resort to that destroys its appeal to potential converts. That strategy is designed only to keep Christians from leaving, not spread the faith. That mission was already killed by losing the argument. All the rabbit holes after that just reveal how screwed the Christian is, exposing the lengths they have to go to to avoid admitting that. Which is not a good look to outsiders. But even those who care whether the rabbit holes get anywhere will find, of course, that they do not. They all end the same way.

For example, atheists are judging the Christian God here by the Christian’s own moral standards, and thus the observed internal incoherence cannot be escaped by complaining that atheists have nothing to replace it with. You cannot claim atheists don’t get to use the word “evil,” because it’s the Christian who is making these claims about their God, and the atheist is simply pointing out that their own definitions entail fatal contradictions in their entire worldview. But also, of course, it isn’t true anyway. Atheists can certainly use the word “evil,” because they have a universal definition all peoples, of all religions and none, agree with, and which makes or entails no appeal to gods or the supernatural: evil is simply any malignancy or malevolence. If it causes needless suffering, we disapprove of it. And so, even if you should insist that atheists can only say this is a subjective opinion, it remains true as a subjective opinion: if we disapprove of needless suffering, and your God inflicts needless suffering, we cannot approve of your God. You therefore aren’t going to sell us on him. You are just stumping for Hitler. However much you insist “But Hitler was right” isn’t going to appeal. It’s just going to make us dislike you even more.

Ultimately, trying to sell a gross and toxic religion, once it is exposed as gross and toxic, simply isn’t going to work. Your religion’s days are numbered, once that curtain is pulled and everyone sees it as malignant. That’s why you need all those dubious apologetics to try and rescue your slavemaster God from being evil, rather than simply admitting evil is the new good. And that is why single-point slam-dunks like Dillahunty’s point, that God cannot be both good and someone who endorsed slavery, are so effective: they isolate the problem to a single point, thus preventing Christians from hiding in a maze of constant subject-changes, allowing them to disguise any apologetic as sound. With a single point of focus, it is easier to keep pointing out that none of their excuses are logical, and only further expose the bankruptcy of their entire worldview. And audiences of all intellectual levels will start to see that (as long as you don’t fall for their trick of changing the subject, but stay ever-on-point).

The Point about Plantinga

In Is a Good God Logically Impossible? I analyzed James Sterba’s already-decisive refutation of Plantinga’s Free Will Defense against the Argument from Evil thus:

Allowing freedom actually consequentially results in greatly reducing it.

For example, allowing tyrants freedom to take power and oppress a population results in a vast net reduction in freedom. If physically restraining me from doing my will violates my free will, then allowing someone to physically restrain me violates my free will. God therefore cannot use “free will” as an excuse not to intervene. To the contrary, if “free will” is really so supremely important, that fact would compel him to intervene a great deal more than he is observed to do, specifically in order to maximize the abundance of free will.

After all, a free society contains more unrestrained free will than an oppressed one, obviously. That one must violate some free will to maintain a free society is a logically necessary fact (e.g. tyrants, killers, slavers must be thwarted in their designs); but if the goal is to reduce violations of free will, a good ruler must do this. Not doing so has the opposite result—and thus cannot be justified by any principle on which maximizing free will is the greater good.

One could extend this even to natural evils—which [Plantinga’s] Free-Will Defense has never plausibly accounted for. Indeed Sterba has a closing chapter on natural evil that addresses the difficulties it adds to theism. Merely among which are the fact that such evils produce violations of free will on a massive scale: killing people without their consent certainly violates their free will; as does inflicting them with disease; crippling someone without their consent—especially mentally but more obviously also when physically—certainly impedes their freedoms, no differently than binding them in chains or beating them with sticks; taking away one’s hard-earned property by disaster leaves them less free than people who were able to avoid that same fate by having access to protective resources; and so on. If a good God really would value “free will” above all else, then we would not see the world around us that we do—directly contrary to Plantinga’s thesis. His excuse is thus self-refuting. It leads not to a justification of god, but to an even more glaring logical contradiction between his god as-defined and what we observe.

Sterba demonstrates this result holds even for moral evil…

Sterba further points out that thwarting the effects of immoral acts does not even qualify as violating anyone’s free will. Making me invulnerable to disease with a vaccine does not violate my free will. Just as making me invulnerable to a murderer’s bullets would not. Which means God’s just making us all immune to disease wouldn’t violate anyone’s free will, and thus his failure to do so cannot be justified. But it would not even violate a murderer’s will to make me as immune to bullets as to disease—any more than putting me in a bullet proof vest would. No one would dare argue bullet proof vests are immoral and should be banned because they violate the free will of gunmen who wish to shoot at people. They can shoot at them all they want. Their will is free. Their evil is also thwarted. The Free-Will Defense is thus defunct. It can no more justify God, than it would justify you preventing anyone wearing a bullet proof vest. Indeed your doing so would make you evil, not good. Plantinga’s argument thus does likewise to God.

The perverse flaw in Platinga’s Free-Will Defense is that it entails a nightmarish anarcho-libertarian worldview wherein if I have the physical means to kill or abuse you, I therefore in effect have the moral right to do so, because no one ought take any measure to stop me—in fact it would be their doing so that’s evil, not the act of a good person. Because maintaining my freedom is a greater good than thwarting my victim’s fate. But this flips around the entire meaning of good and evil, turning every act we deem good, evil; and every act we deem evil, good.

Plantinga’s Free-Will Defense is thus another semantic trick: he actually is defining his god as a horrific monster, and simply “chooses” to call being a horrific monster “good.” All just to avoid admitting to himself that he admires a horrific monster. Placing freedom above justice quite simply is evil. For evil is by definition the absence of justice. Just as placing freedom above respecting people’s well being is the absence of goodness, precisely because respecting people’s well being is what goodness means. Freedom is only good when thwarting it would do more harm than exercising it, thus we thwart murder but not speech, rape but not consent, theft but not commerce, and so on; recognizing this distinction is literally what goodness and justice are.

Sterba thus shows that Plantinga’s god as-defined cannot be good. It is a logical impossibility. Therefore one must abandon that definition and retreat to some other conception of a good god, for there to be any logical possibility of one.

This is a powerful point. And it is conclusive. But you will notice it’s long and has many parts. And I’m just summarizing Sterba’s case, which is chapters long, not just paragraphs. This is no discredit to my summary or his argument. We’re just respecting the truth and being as thorough as the medium allows. But notice how it affords many escape routes to the lazy or the delusional. It takes work to vet what we’ve said and honestly think through any knee-jerk reactions to it you may have. It provides many opportunities to avoid the conclusion by nitpicking some minor detail, and constantly changing the subject, so as to avoid ever admitting (or even realizing) that you are cornered. It has lots of rabbit holes to flee into, numerous semantic tricks to playground in, and all the other strategies people employ to avoid confronting what they’ve just been told.

But there is a way to Dillahunty this.

And that comes from my article How Not to Live in Zardoz. I realized this a while ago when I started linking to that article when making the point that we already know what more morally designed worlds would look like—and it isn’t the one we are in. In my Zardoz article I set aside the whole ridiculous debate over spaceghosts and ask a more practical question: when we atheists do eventually create the only possible eternal heaven that there will be, how do we prevent it becoming a hell? The answer is, really, the same as any moral God would have arrived at. Because God by definition would have far more resources, and far less fallibility, than human engineers, and thus could only do the same thing better. It therefore is no longer arguable that he “had” to do it so much worse (as our present world is, by comparison with what well-designed simworlds can be).

I won’t belabor all the ways this is true—though, per my strategic point, we should do that, just not here, as here we are talking about persuasion, not learning, and one needs first be persuaded before they will be willing to learn. I will instead take one single point from my Zardoz article: the safe room. Which I detailed there under the heading of the “Law of Inviolable Escape” but can summarize here as: every person, whenever they themselves choose, can teleport to an inviolable safe room, where they will be comfortable and their basic needs met, and no villain can reach them (and this is by the individual’s choice, hence exercising their free will that God is supposed to respect). Let’s suppose that this comes with one other rule, which is that whenever you choose to leave your safe room, you will be teleported to a relatively safe spot in a randomly selected city, and thus have to make your way home (or to the authorities or whatever else). And we’ll call those two rules the Saferoom Law.

Now, imagine our world, and an alternative one identical in every way (every single way), but one: that world is governed by one more law of physics, the Saferoom Law. And assume each world was created by a God. In which world is that God more moral? There is no honest way around the answer: that non-existent God is more moral. Which entails any existent God cannot be moral.

Mic drop. You’re done.

You can’t get around this with Plantinga’s defense, because the world governed by the Saferoom Law preserves more free will than our world does. Victims have the free will to escape villains. And there is nothing logically impossible about the Saferoom Law. We will be able to enact it when we make our worlds (the simworlds, or virtual worlds, we will eventually some day live in). And we are far less capable than God. So God has no excuse not to have commanded our world obey the Saferoom Law. You can’t defend this by saying villains should have the right to victimize people, because that simply isn’t true. Villains may have the right to freely choose to attack people; but they do not have the right to kill or harm them thereby. On no moral theory (especially the Christian’s own moral theory) is it moral to enable the wills of villains at the expense of the wills of victims. In that context, the only free will it is moral to preserve is the victim’s. And so on down the line: no matter what excuse you come up with (no matter what rabbit hole you attempt to flee into), the same end will befall you. I recently went through the rubbish heap of Christian attempts to explain away evil in Which Is ‘Rational’: Theism or Atheism? In every case, if you think it through, you’ll realize none of them can explain why our world is not governed by the Saferoom Law—if it was designed by a morally good God.

In the Saferoom World, villains still have the free will to choose villainy, while victims have the free will to escape it. No one’s will, really, is violated at all. And even if you try to push the point that the villain’s freedom to succeed is being thwarted (which is not the same thing), in any contest between who, morally, should succeed, a villain or a victim, there is no moral way to argue it’s the villain and not the victim. You would then just be defending villainy. Just like defending God as a slavemaster admits he is evil, so defending God as an aider-and-abetter of villains and thwarter of victims admits he is evil. To then call this evil “good” is simply a semantic trick no one half-awake is going to fall for. You might be able to sustain your own delusion with such irrational moves, but you will only be destroying your religion’s credibility in the eyes of outsiders.

It also will not do any good to complain that there is still “evil” in the Saferoom World (it doesn’t stop theft or disease, for example; and saferoomers still face some inconvenience of relocation that villains can nevertheless exploit; and so on), because the point of this one argument is that a Saferoom World is logically possible yet less evil than our world. That’s enough to prove no good God exists. Everything else is just a quibble over how good a God need be to qualify, which I effectively address in the rest of my Zardoz article. That’s the learning part of this equation. But to start with the persuasion part, it’s enough to force a Christian to stay on this one single point and not evade it by running away, changing the subject, straw manning the example, or any other device. Once this breaks through their delusion (if ever it does), then they will have the motivation to take the time to explore the rest of the equation (and ask, really, honestly, what a world would look like that actually was built by a moral person).

Conclusion

Three points have been made here. One, the strategic difference between persuasion and learning. Two, how to apply this by extending Dillahunty’s single-subject “slavery” argument against the existence of a good God into a single-subject Saferoom argument against the existence of a good God. And three, that once one escapes their delusion and realizes God is implausible, there is much left to learn about how to build a morally just world (rather than foolishly defend as moral the amoral one we live in). But, “Big Picture,” you need to realize that any Argument from Evil against God is, really, a refutation of the Design Argument. There are nonmoral points of bad design that prove our world cannot have been intelligently designed (I outline several in Bayesian Counter-Apologetics and Ten Ways the World Would Be Different If God Existed). But the moral points apply to any claim that the designer is good, and thus worthy of respect and allegiance (rather than disgust and disregard).

Since no one believes in malevolent gods anymore, because modern people only believe out of an emotional desire that there be a good God (theism is thus now a delusion, and not, as once it was, a mere epistemic error), refuting the goodness of God is the gateway drug to escaping that delusion and realizing there is no god at all, of any character. And then we can get to the business of admitting the only thing we have is each other, and the world we design and maintain. And then rather than wait around for a non-existent savior and a non-existent immortality in a non-existent paradise, we can get cracking on investing in saving each other, and building our own paradises to live our extended blessed lives in. We might not see that world ourselves. But we could be working to build it for our children, or their children. And that’s better than it never existing at all.

Which you must agree with, if you believe living in a future paradise is a moral good worth helping others to—which all Christians must already believe in…if they are not liars or hypocrites. Although, experience tells us, quite a few are. But the rest can be saved.

-:-

Christians keen on learning why the claims of their mental slavemasters are all lies, such as that abandoning that faith entails abandoning moral goodness and every other real thing of value, will benefit from reading my entire series on Justin Brierley.

§

To comment use the Add Comment field at bottom, or click the Reply box next to (or the nearest one above) any comment. See Comments & Moderation Policy for standards and expectations.

Share this:

Discover more from Richard Carrier Blogs

Subscribe now to keep reading and get access to the full archive.

Continue reading